Thank you for visiting nature.com. You are using a browser version with limited support for CSS. To obtain the best experience, we recommend you use a more up to date browser (or turn off compatibility mode in Internet Explorer). In the meantime, to ensure continued support, we are displaying the site without styles and JavaScript.

  • View all journals
  • Explore content
  • About the journal
  • Publish with us
  • Sign up for alerts
  • Review Article
  • Published: 22 August 2023

Insights into embodied cognition and mental imagery from aphantasia

  • Emiko J. Muraki   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-9534-6538 1 , 2 ,
  • Laura J. Speed   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-3147-3615 3 &
  • Penny M. Pexman   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-7130-0973 1 , 2  

Nature Reviews Psychology volume  2 ,  pages 591–605 ( 2023 ) Cite this article

1134 Accesses

1 Citations

31 Altmetric

Metrics details

  • Behavioural methods
  • Language and linguistics

Mental representations allow humans to think about, remember and communicate about an infinite number of concepts. A key question within cognitive psychology is how the mind stores and accesses the meaning of concepts. Embodied theories propose that concept knowledge includes or requires simulations of the sensory and physical interactions of one’s body with the world, even when a concept is subsequently processed in a context unrelated to those interactions. However, the nature of these simulations is highly debated and their mechanisms underspecified. Insight into whether and how simulations support concept knowledge can be derived from studying related mental representations, such as mental imagery. In particular, research into the inability to form mental imagery, known as aphantasia, can advance understanding of mental imagery and mental simulations. In this Review, we provide an overview of embodied theories of cognition, review research in mental imagery and consider how simulation and mental imagery might overlap. We then synthesize the growing aphantasia literature and discuss how aphantasia can be used to test predictions derived from theories of embodied cognition.

This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution

Access options

Subscribe to this journal

Receive 12 digital issues and online access to articles

55,14 € per year

only 4,60 € per issue

Buy this article

  • Purchase on Springer Link
  • Instant access to full article PDF

Prices may be subject to local taxes which are calculated during checkout

another name for a mental representation is cognitive sketch

Similar content being viewed by others

another name for a mental representation is cognitive sketch

Microdosing with psilocybin mushrooms: a double-blind placebo-controlled study

another name for a mental representation is cognitive sketch

Maximum diffusion reinforcement learning

another name for a mental representation is cognitive sketch

The development of human causal learning and reasoning

Pearson, J., Naselaris, T., Holmes, E. A. & Kosslyn, S. M. Mental imagery: functional mechanisms and clinical applications. Trends Cogn. Sci. 19 , 590–602 (2015).

Article   PubMed   PubMed Central   Google Scholar  

Zeman, A. Z. J. et al. Loss of imagery phenomenology with intact visuo-spatial task performance: a case of ‘blind imagination’. Neuropsychologia 48 , 145–155 (2010).

Article   PubMed   Google Scholar  

Zeman, A., Dewar, M. & Della Sala, S. Lives without imagery — congenital aphantasia. Cortex 73 , 378–380 (2015). This article is among the first to describe and characterize congenital aphantasia, the lifelong absence of mental imagery.

Wilson, M. Six views of embodied cognition. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 9 , 625–636 (2002).

Barsalou, L. W. Grounded cognition. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 59 , 617–645 (2008). This article describes the theoretical foundation of embodied cognition as it relates to several cognitive processes and reviews the empirical literature testing embodied theories of cognition.

Mahon, B. Z. & Caramazza, A. A critical look at the embodied cognition hypothesis and a new proposal for grounding conceptual content. J. Physiol.-Paris 102 , 59–70 (2008).

Ostarek, M. & Bottini, R. Towards strong inference in research on embodiment — possibilities and limitations of causal paradigms. J. Cogn. 4 , 1–21 (2020). This article critiques empirical evidence for embodied conceptual processing and proposes methodological approaches to better understand the causal relationship between sensory experience and conceptual processing.

Google Scholar  

Dawes, A. J., Keogh, R., Robuck, S. & Pearson, J. Memories with a blind mind: remembering the past and imagining the future with aphantasia. Cognition 227 , 105192 (2022).

Fodor, J. A. The Language of Thought Vol. 5 (Harvard Univ. Press, 1975).

Pylyshyn, Z. Computation and cognition: issues in the foundations of cognitive science. Behav. Brain Sci. 3 , 111–169 (1980).

Article   Google Scholar  

Anderson, J. R. Arguments concerning representations for mental imagery. Psychol. Rev. 85 , 249–277 (1978).

Pylyshyn, Z. W. What the mind’s eye tells the mind’s brain: a critique of mental imagery. Psychol. Bull. 80 , 1–24 (1973).

Zwaan, R. A. The immersed experiencer: toward an embodied theory of language comprehension. Psychol. Learn. Motiv. 44 , 35–62 (2004).

Meteyard, L., Cuadrado, S. R., Bahrami, B. & Vigliocco, G. Coming of age: a review of embodiment and the neuroscience of semantics. Cortex 48 , 788–804 (2012). This article describes the spectrum of theories related to embodied and non-embodied semantic representation, linking behavioural and neural evidence with the theories.

Collins, A. M. & Loftus, E. F. A spreading-activation theory of semantic processing. Psychol. Rev. 82 , 407 (1975).

Quillian, M. R. Word concepts: a theory and simulation of some basic semantic capabilities. Behav. Sci. 12 , 410–430 (1967).

Quillian, R. A revised design for an understanding machine. Mech. Transl. 7 , 17–29 (1962).

Patterson, K. & Lambon Ralph, M. A. in Neurobiology of Language Ch. 61 (eds Hickok, G. & Small, S. L.) 765–775 (Academic, 2016).

Barsalou, L. W., Santos, A., Simmons, W. K. & Wilson, C. D. in Symbols, Embodiment, and Meaning (eds De Vega, M., Glenberg, A. M. & Graesser, A. C.) 245–283 (Oxford Univ. Press, 2008).

Connell, L. What have labels ever done for us? The linguistic shortcut in conceptual processing. Lang. Cogn. Neurosci. 34 , 1308–1318 (2019).

Paivio, A. Imagery and Verbal Processes (Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1971).

Paivio, A. Mental imagery in associative learning and memory. Psychol. Rev. 76 , 241–263 (1969).

Balota, D. A., Cortese, M. J., Sergent-Marshall, S. D., Spieler, D. H. & Yap, M. J. Visual word recognition of single-syllable words. J. Exp. Psychol.-Gen. 133 , 283–316 (2004).

Barsalou, L. W. Perceptual symbol systems. Behav. Brain Sci. 22 , 577–660 (1999).

Glenberg, A. M. & Gallese, V. Action-based language: a theory of language acquisition, comprehension, and production. Cortex 48 , 905–922 (2012).

Brysbaert, M., Warriner, A. B. & Kuperman, V. Concreteness ratings for 40 thousand generally known English word lemmas. Behav. Res. Methods 46 , 904–911 (2014).

Lynott, D., Connell, L., Brysbaert, M., Brand, J. & Carney, J. The lancaster sensorimotor norms: multidimensional measures of perceptual and action strength for 40,000 English words. Behav. Res. Methods 52 , 1271–1291 (2020).

Pexman, P. M., Muraki, E., Sidhu, D. M., Siakaluk, P. D. & Yap, M. J. Quantifying sensorimotor experience: body-object interaction ratings for more than 9,000 English words. Behav. Res. Methods 51 , 453–466 (2019).

Balota, D. A. et al. The English Lexicon Project. Behav. Res. Methods 39 , 445–459 (2007).

Siakaluk, P. D., Pexman, P. M., Aguilera, L., Owen, W. J. & Sears, C. R. Evidence for the activation of sensorimotor information during visual word recognition: the body–object interaction effect. Cognition 106 , 433–443 (2008).

Sidhu, D. M., Kwan, R., Pexman, P. M. & Siakaluk, P. D. Effects of relative embodiment in lexical and semantic processing of verbs. Acta Psychol. 149 , 32–39 (2014).

Pecher, D., Zeelenberg, R. & Barsalou, L. W. Verifying different-modality properties for concepts produces switching costs. Psychol. Sci. 14 , 119–124 (2003).

Pecher, D., Zeelenberg, R. & Barsalou, L. W. Sensorimotor simulations underlie conceptual representations: modality-specific effects of prior activation. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 11 , 164–167 (2004).

Dove, G. Three symbol ungrounding problems: abstract concepts and the future of embodied cognition. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 23 , 1109–1121 (2016).

Louwerse, M. M. Symbol interdependency in symbolic and embodied cognition. Top. Cogn. Sci. 3 , 273–302 (2011).

Glenberg, A. M. & Kaschak, M. P. Grounding language in action. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 9 , 558–565 (2002).

Stanfield, R. A. & Zwaan, R. The effect of implied orientation derived from verbal context on picture recognition. Psychol. Sci. 12 , 153–156 (2001).

Morey, R. D. et al. A pre-registered, multi-lab non-replication of the action-sentence compatibility effect (ACE). Psychon. Bull. Rev. 29 , 613–626 (2021).

Winter, A. The action–sentence compatibility effect (ACE): meta-analysis of a benchmark finding for embodiment. Acta Psychol. 230 , 103712 (2022).

Muraki, E. J. & Pexman, P. M. Simulating semantics: are individual differences in motor imagery related to sensorimotor effects in language processing? J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn. 47 , 1939–1957 (2021).

Zwaan, R. A. & Pecher, D. Revisiting mental simulation in language comprehension: six replication attempts. PLoS ONE 7 , e51382 (2012).

Beveridge, M. E. L. & Pickering, M. J. Perspective taking in language: integrating the spatial and action domains. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 7 , 577 (2013).

Hargreaves, I. S., White, M., Pexman, P. M., Pittman, D. & Goodyear, B. G. The question shapes the answer: the neural correlates of task differences reveal dynamic semantic processing. Brain Lang. 120 , 73–78 (2012).

Tousignant, C. & Pexman, P. Flexible recruitment of semantic richness: context modulates body–object interaction effects in lexical-semantic processing. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 6 , 7 (2012).

van Dam, W. O., van Dijk, M., Bekkering, H. & Rueschemeyer, S.-A. Flexibility in embodied lexical-semantic representations. Hum. Brain Mapp. 33 , 2322–2333 (2012).

Reifegerste, J., Meyer, A. S., Zwitserlood, P. & Ullman, M. T. Aging affects steaks more than knives: evidence that the processing of words related to motor skills is relatively spared in aging. Brain Lang. 218 , 104941 (2021).

Simonsen, H. G., Lind, M., Hansen, P., Holm, E. & Mevik, B. H. Imageability of Norwegian nouns, verbs and adjectives in a cross-linguistic perspective. Clin. Linguist. Phon. 27 , 435–446 (2013).

Ibáñez, A. et al. Ecological meanings: a consensus paper on individual differences and contextual influences in embodied language. Preprint at OSF https://osf.io/ej5y3/ (2022).

Andrews, M., Vigliocco, G. & Vinson, D. Integrating experiential and distributional data to learn semantic representations. Psychol. Rev. 116 , 463–498 (2009).

Banks, B., Wingfield, C. & Connell, L. Linguistic distributional knowledge and sensorimotor grounding both contribute to semantic category production. Cogn. Sci. 45 , e13055 (2021).

Henningsen-Schomers, M. R., Garagnani, M. & Pulvermüller, F. Influence of language on perception and concept formation in a brain-constrained deep neural network model. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 378 , 20210373 (2023).

Barsalou, L. W. Challenges and opportunities for grounding cognition. J. Cogn. 3 , 31 (2020).

Ostarek, M. & Huettig, F. A task-dependent causal role for low-level visual processes in spoken word comprehension. J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn. 43 , 1215–1224 (2017).

Kuhnke, P., Beaupain, M. C., Arola, J., Kiefer, M. & Hartwigsen, G. Meta-analytic evidence for a novel hierarchical model of conceptual processing. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev . 144 , 104994 (2022). This article reports a meta-analysis examining the role of modal regions in conceptual processing.

Gallese, V. Mirror neurons and the social nature of language: the neural exploitation hypothesis. Soc. Neurosci. 3 , 317–333 (2008).

Pulvermüller, F. Semantic embodiment, disembodiment or misembodiment? In search of meaning in modules and neuron circuits. Brain Lang. 127 , 86–103 (2013).

Barsalou, L. W. On staying grounded and avoiding quixotic dead ends. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 23 , 1122–1142 (2016).

Barsalou, L. W. Establishing generalizable mechanisms. Psychol. Inq. 30 , 220–230 (2019).

Bottini, R., Morucci, P., D’Urso, A., Collignon, O. & Crepaldi, D. The concreteness advantage in lexical decision does not depend on perceptual simulations. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen. 151 , 731–738 (2022).

Boulenger, V. et al. Word processing in Parkinson’s disease is impaired for action verbs but not for concrete nouns. Neuropsychologia 46 , 743–756 (2008).

Buccino, G. et al. Processing graspable object images and their nouns is impaired in Parkinson’s disease patients. Cortex 100 , 32–39 (2018).

García, A. M. et al. Parkinson’s disease compromises the appraisal of action meanings evoked by naturalistic texts. Cortex 100 , 111–126 (2018).

García, A. M. et al. How language flows when movements don’t: an automated analysis of spontaneous discourse in Parkinson’s disease. Brain Lang. 162 , 19–28 (2016).

Nistico, R. et al. The embodiment of language in tremor-dominant Parkinson’s disease patients. Brain Cogn. 135 , 103586 (2019).

Trumpp, N. M., Kliese, D., Hoenig, K., Haarmeier, T. & Kiefer, M. Losing the sound of concepts: damage to auditory association cortex impairs the processing of sound-related concepts. Cortex 49 , 474–486 (2013).

Kim, J. S., Elli, G. V. & Bedny, M. Knowledge of animal appearance among sighted and blind adults. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 116 , 11213–11222 (2019).

Lewis, M., Zettersten, M. & Lupyan, G. Distributional semantics as a source of visual knowledge. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 116 , 19237–19238 (2019).

Nanay, B. Multimodal mental imagery. Cortex 105 , 125–134 (2018).

Pearson, J. The human imagination: the cognitive neuroscience of visual mental imagery. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 20 , 624–634 (2019). This article provides an overview of the neural bases of visual imagery.

Pearson, J. & Westbrook, F. Phantom perception: voluntary and involuntary nonretinal vision. Trends Cogn. Sci. 19 , 278–284 (2015).

Kwok, E. L., Leys, G., Koenig-Robert, R. & Pearson, J. Measuring thought-control failure: sensory mechanisms and individual differences. Psychol. Sci. 30 , 811–821 (2019).

Jeannerod, M. Neural simulation of action: a unifying mechanism for motor cognition. Neuroimage 14 , S103–S109 (2001).

Willems, R. M., Toni, I., Hagoort, P. & Casasanto, D. Neural dissociations between action verb understanding and motor imagery. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 22 , 2387–2400 (2009).

Connell, L. & Lynott, D. Do we know what we’re simulating? Information loss on transferring unconscious perceptual simulation to conscious imagery. J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn. 42 , 1218–1232 (2016).

Pearson, J. & Kosslyn, S. M. The heterogeneity of mental representation: ending the imagery debate. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA   112 , 10089–10092 (2015).

Kosslyn, S. M., Ganis, G. & Thompson, W. L. Neural foundations of imagery. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 2 , 635–642 (2001).

Keogh, R. & Pearson, J. The perceptual and phenomenal capacity of mental imagery. Cognition 162 , 124–132 (2017).

Pearson, J., Clifford, C. W. G. & Tong, F. The functional impact of mental imagery on conscious perception. Curr. Biol. 18 , 982–986 (2008).

Brascamp, J. W., Knapen, T. H. J., Kanai, R., Van Ee, R. & Van Den Berg, A. V. Flash suppression and flash facilitation in binocular rivalry. J. Vis. 7 , 12 (2007).

Chang, S., Lewis, D. E. & Pearson, J. The functional effects of color perception and color imagery. J. Vis. 13 , 4–4 (2013).

Kosslyn, S. M. Scanning visual images: some structural implications. Percept. Psychophys. 14 , 90–94 (1973).

Kosslyn, S. M. Information representation in visual images. Cognit. Psychol. 7 , 341–370 (1975).

Kosslyn, S. M. Can imagery be distinguished from other forms of internal representation? Evidence from studies of information retrieval times. Mem. Cognit. 4 , 291–297 (1976).

Parsons, L. M. Imagined spatial transformations of one’s hands and feet. Cognit. Psychol. 19 , 178–241 (1987).

Shepard, R. N. & Metzler, J. Mental rotation of three-dimensional objects. Science 171 , 701–703 (1971).

Shepard, S. & Metzler, D. Mental rotation: effects of dimensionality of objects and type of task. J. Exp. Psychol. Hum. Percept. Perform. 14 , 3–11 (1988).

Kosslyn, S. M. & Pomerantz, J. R. Imagery, propositions, and the form of internal representations. Cognit. Psychol. 9 , 52–76 (1977).

Albers, A. M., Kok, P., Toni, I., Dijkerman, H. C. & de Lange, F. P. Shared representations for working memory and mental imagery in early visual cortex. Curr. Biol. 23 , 1427–1431 (2013).

Stokes, M., Thompson, R., Cusack, R. & Duncan, J. Top-down activation of shape-specific population codes in visual cortex during mental imagery. J. Neurosci. 29 , 1565–1572 (2009).

Harrison, S. A. & Tong, F. Decoding reveals the contents of visual working memory in early visual areas. Nature 458 , 632–635 (2009).

Kosslyn, S. M. et al. The role of area 17 in visual imagery: convergent evidence from PET and rTMS. Science 284 , 167–170 (1999).

Cui, X., Jeter, C. B., Yang, D., Montague, P. R. & Eagleman, D. M. Vividness of mental imagery: individual variability can be measured objectively. Vis. Res. 47 , 474–478 (2007).

Dijkstra, N., Zeidman, P., Ondobaka, S., van Gerven, M. A. J. & Friston, K. Distinct top-down and bottom-up brain connectivity during visual perception and imagery. Sci. Rep. 7 , 5677 (2017).

Bensafi, M., Rinck, F., Schaal, B. & Rouby, C. Verbal cues modulate hedonic perception of odors in 5-year-old children as well as in adults. Chem. Senses 32 , 855–862 (2007).

Djordjevic, J., Zatorre, R. J., Petrides, M., Boyle, J. A. & Jones-Gotman, M. Functional neuroimaging of odor imagery. NeuroImage 24 , 791–801 (2005).

Bunzeck, N., Wuestenberg, T., Lutz, K., Heinze, H. J. & Jancke, L. Scanning silence: mental imagery of complex sounds. NeuroImage 26 , 1119–1127 (2005).

Hubbard, T. L. Auditory imagery: empirical findings. Psychol. Bull. 136 , 302–329 (2010).

Schmidt, T. T., Ostwald, D. & Blankenburg, F. Imaging tactile imagery: changes in brain connectivity support perceptual grounding of mental images in primary sensory cortices. NeuroImage 98 , 216–224 (2014).

Schmidt, T. T. & Blankenburg, F. The somatotopy of mental tactile imagery. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 13 , 10 (2019).

Yoo, S.-S., Freeman, D. K., McCarthy, J. J. & Jolesz, F. A. Neural substrates of tactile imagery: a functional MRI study. NeuroReport 14 , 581–585 (2003).

Gerardin, E. Partially overlapping neural networks for real and imagined hand movements. Cereb. Cortex 10 , 1093–1104 (2000).

Hardwick, R. M., Caspers, S., Eickhoff, S. B. & Swinnen, S. P. Neural correlates of action: comparing meta-analyses of imagery, observation, and execution. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 94 , 31–44 (2018).

Linke, A. C. & Cusack, R. Flexible information coding in human auditory cortex during perception, imagery, and STM of complex sounds. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 27 , 1322–1333 (2015).

Plailly, J., Delon-Martin, C. & Royet, J. P. Experience induces functional reorganization in brain regions involved in odor imagery in perfumers. Hum. Brain Mapp. 33 , 224–234 (2012).

Alemanno, F. et al. Action-related semantic content and negation polarity modulate motor areas during sentence reading: an event-related desynchronization study. Brain Res. 1484 , 39–49 (2012).

Bechtold, L., Ghio, M., Lange, J. & Bellebaum, C. Event-related desynchronization of mu and beta oscillations during the processing of novel tool names. Brain Lang. 177–178 , 44–55 (2018).

Moreno, I., de Vega, M. & León, I. Understanding action language modulates oscillatory mu and beta rhythms in the same way as observing actions. Brain Cogn. 82 , 236–242 (2013).

Moreno, I. et al. Brain dynamics in the comprehension of action-related language. a time-frequency analysis of mu rhythms. NeuroImage 109 , 50–62 (2015).

Niccolai, V. et al. Grasping hand verbs: oscillatory beta and alpha correlates of action-word processing. PLoS ONE 9 , e108059 (2014).

van Elk, M., van Schie, H. T., Zwaan, R. A. & Bekkering, H. The functional role of motor activation in language processing: motor cortical oscillations support lexical-semantic retrieval. NeuroImage 50 , 665–677 (2010).

Cayol, Z., Rotival, C., Paulignan, Y. & Nazir, T. A. “Embodied” language processing: mental motor imagery aptitude predicts word-definition skill for high but not for low imageable words in adolescents. Brain Cogn. 145 , 105628 (2020).

McKelvie, S. J. & Demers, E. G. Individual differences in reported visual imagery and memory performance. Br. J. Psychol. 70 , 51–57 (1979).

Bonnet, C. et al. Kinesthetic motor-imagery training improves performance on lexical-semantic access. PLoS ONE 17 , e0270352 (2022).

Pecher, D., van Dantzig, S. & Schifferstein, H. N. J. Concepts are not represented by conscious imagery. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 16 , 914–919 (2009).

Speed, L. J. & Majid, A. An exception to mental simulation: no evidence for embodied odor language. Cogn. Sci. 42 , 1146–1178 (2018).

Keogh, R., Pearson, J. & Zeman, A. in Handbook of Clinical Neurology vol. 178 (eds. Barton, J. J. S. & Leff, A.) 277–296 (Elsevier, 2021). This chapter provides a review of the extremes of visual imagery and current research on aphantasia and hyperphantasia.

Dance, C. J., Ipser, A. & Simner, J. The prevalence of aphantasia (imagery weakness) in the general population. Conscious. Cogn. 10 , 103243 (2022).

Zeman, A. et al. Phantasia — the psychological significance of lifelong visual imagery vividness extremes. Cortex 130 , 426–440 (2020).

Milton, F. et al. Behavioral and neural signatures of visual imagery vividness extremes: aphantasia versus hyperphantasia. Cereb. Cortex Commun. 2 , tgab035 (2021).

Farah, M. J., Hammond, K. M., Levine, D. N. & Calvanio, R. Visual and spatial mental imagery: dissociable systems of representation. Cognit. Psychol. 20 , 439–462 (1988).

Marks, D. F. Visual imagery differences in the recall of pictures. Br. J. Psychol. 64 , 17–24 (1973).

Dance, C. J., Ward, J. & Simner, J. What is the link between mental imagery and sensory sensitivity? Insights from aphantasia. Perception 50 , 757–782 (2021).

Dawes, A. J., Keogh, R., Andrillon, T. & Pearson, J. A cognitive profile of multi-sensory imagery, memory and dreaming in aphantasia. Sci. Rep. 10 , 10022 (2020).

Keogh, R. Visual working memory in aphantasia: retained accuracy and capacity with a different strategy. Cortex 143 , 237–253 (2021).

Wicken, M., Keogh, R. & Pearson, J. The critical role of mental imagery in human emotion: insights from fear-based imagery and aphantasia. Proc. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 288 , 20210267 (2021).

Bainbridge, W. A., Pounder, Z., Eardley, A. F. & Baker, C. I. Quantifying aphantasia through drawing: those without visual imagery show deficits in object but not spatial memory. Cortex 135 , 159–172 (2021).

Monzel, M., Keidel, K. & Reuter, M. Imagine, and you will find — lack of attentional guidance through visual imagery in aphantasics. Atten. Percept. Psychophys. 83 , 2486–2497 (2021).

Keogh, R. & Pearson, J. The blind mind: no sensory visual imagery in aphantasia. Cortex 105 , 53–60 (2018).

Kay, L., Keogh, R., Andrillon, T. & Pearson, J. The pupillary light response as a physiological index of aphantasia, sensory and phenomenological imagery strength. eLife 11 , e72484 (2022).

Visser, I. et al. Improving the generalizability of infant psychological research: the ManyBabies model. Behav. Brain Sci. 45 , e35 (2022).

Takahashi, J. et al. Diversity of aphantasia revealed by multiple assessments of visual imagery, multisensory imagery, and cognitive style. Front. Psychol. 14 , 1174873 (2023).

Blajenkova, O., Kozhevnikov, M. & Motes, M. A. Object-spatial imagery: a new self-report imagery questionnaire. Appl. Cogn. Psychol. 20 , 239–263 (2006).

Palermo, L., Boccia, M., Piccardi, L. & Nori, R. Congenital lack and extraordinary ability in object and spatial imagery: an investigation on sub-types of aphantasia and hyperphantasia. Conscious. Cogn. 103 , 103360 (2022).

Jacobs, C., Schwarzkopf, D. S. & Silvanto, J. Visual working memory performance in aphantasia. Cortex 105 , 61–73 (2018).

Monzel, M., Vetterlein, A. & Reuter, M. Memory deficits in aphantasics are not restricted to autobiographical memory — perspectives from the dual coding approach. J. Neuropsychol. 16 , 444–461 (2022).

Fulford, J. et al. The neural correlates of visual imagery vividness — an fMRI study and literature review. Cortex 105 , 26–40 (2018).

Speed, L. J. & Majid, A. Grounding language in the neglected senses of touch, taste, and smell. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 37 , 363–392 (2020).

Hald, L. A., van den Hurk, M. & Bekkering, H. Learning verbs more effectively through meaning congruent action animations. Learn. Instr. 39 , 107–122 (2015).

James, K. H. & Swain, S. N. Only self-generated actions create sensori-motor systems in the developing brain. Dev. Sci. 14 , 673–678 (2011).

Muraki, E. J., Siddiqui, I. A. & Pexman, P. M. Quantifying children’s sensorimotor experience: child body–object interaction ratings for 3359 English words. Behav. Res. Methods 54 , 2864–2877 (2022).

Thill, S. & Twomey, K. E. What’s on the inside counts: a grounded account of concept acquisition and development. Front. Psychol. 7 , 402 (2016).

Pexman, P. M. The role of embodiment in conceptual development. Lang. Cogn. Neurosci. 34 , 1274–1283 (2019).

Cortese, M. J. & Fugett, A. Imageability ratings for 3,000 monosyllabic words. Behav. Res. Methods Instrum. Comput. 36 , 384–387 (2004).

Schock, J., Cortese, M. J. & Khanna, M. M. Imageability estimates for 3,000 disyllabic words. Behav. Res. Methods 44 , 374–379 (2012).

Juhasz, B. J. & Yap, M. J. Sensory experience ratings for over 5,000 mono- and disyllabic words. Behav. Res. Methods 45 , 160–168 (2013).

Brysbaert, M. & New, B. Moving beyond Kucera and Francis: a critical evaluation of current word frequency norms and the introduction of a new and improved word frequency measure for American English. Behav. Res. Methods 41 , 977–990 (2009).

Hoffman, P., Lambon Ralph, M. A. & Rogers, T. T. Semantic diversity: a measure of semantic ambiguity based on variability in the contextual usage of words. Behav. Res. Methods 45 , 718–730 (2013).

Shaoul, C. & Westbury, C. Exploring lexical co-occurrence space using HiDEx. Behav. Res. Methods 42 , 393–413 (2010).

Pounder, Z. et al. Only minimal differences between individuals with congenital aphantasia and those with typical imagery on neuropsychological tasks that involve imagery. Cortex 148 , 180–192 (2022).

Dance, C. J. et al. What is the relationship between aphantasia, synaesthesia and autism? Conscious. Cogn. 89 , 103087 (2021).

Ganczarek, J., Żurawska-Żyła, R. & Rolek, A. “I remember things, but I can’t picture them.” What can a case of aphantasia tell us about imagery and memory? Psychiatr. Psychol. Klin. 20 , 134–141 (2020).

Keogh, R. & Pearson, J. Attention driven phantom vision: measuring the sensory strength of attentional templates and their relation to visual mental imagery and aphantasia. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 376 , 20190688 (2021).

Königsmark, V. T., Bergmann, J. & Reeder, R. R. The Ganzflicker experience: high probability of seeing vivid and complex pseudo-hallucinations with imagery but not aphantasia. Cortex 141 , 522–534 (2021).

Baron-Cohen, S., Wheelwright, S., Skinner, R., Martin, J. & Clubley, E. The Autism-spectrum Quotient (AQ): evidence from Asperger syndrome/high-functioning autism, males and females, scientists and mathematicians. J. Autism Dev. Disord. 31 , 5–17 (2001).

Blomkvist, A. Aphantasia: in search of a theory. Mind Lang . https://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12432 (2022).

Blazhenkova, O. & Pechenkova, E. The two eyes of the blind mind: object vs. spatial aphantasia? Russ. J. Cogn. Sci. 6 , 51–62 (2019).

Download references

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Department of Psychology, University of Calgary, Calgary, Alberta, Canada

Emiko J. Muraki & Penny M. Pexman

Hotchkiss Brain Institute, University of Calgary, Calgary, Alberta, Canada

Centre for Language Studies, Radboud University, Nijmegen, The Netherlands

Laura J. Speed

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Contributions

E.J.M. and P.M.P. conceptualized the paper. All authors contributed substantially to discussion of the content. E.J.M. wrote the article. All authors reviewed and/or edited the manuscript before submission.

Corresponding authors

Correspondence to Emiko J. Muraki or Penny M. Pexman .

Ethics declarations

Competing interests.

The authors declare no competing interests.

Peer review

Peer review information.

Nature Reviews Psychology thanks Laura Bechtold, Leo Dutriaux and Jamie Ward for their contribution to the peer review of this work.

Additional information

Publisher’s note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article.

Muraki, E.J., Speed, L.J. & Pexman, P.M. Insights into embodied cognition and mental imagery from aphantasia. Nat Rev Psychol 2 , 591–605 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1038/s44159-023-00221-9

Download citation

Accepted : 17 July 2023

Published : 22 August 2023

Issue Date : October 2023

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1038/s44159-023-00221-9

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

Quick links

  • Explore articles by subject
  • Guide to authors
  • Editorial policies

Sign up for the Nature Briefing newsletter — what matters in science, free to your inbox daily.

another name for a mental representation is cognitive sketch

  • Search Menu
  • Browse content in Arts and Humanities
  • Browse content in Archaeology
  • Anglo-Saxon and Medieval Archaeology
  • Archaeological Methodology and Techniques
  • Archaeology by Region
  • Archaeology of Religion
  • Archaeology of Trade and Exchange
  • Biblical Archaeology
  • Contemporary and Public Archaeology
  • Environmental Archaeology
  • Historical Archaeology
  • History and Theory of Archaeology
  • Industrial Archaeology
  • Landscape Archaeology
  • Mortuary Archaeology
  • Prehistoric Archaeology
  • Underwater Archaeology
  • Urban Archaeology
  • Zooarchaeology
  • Browse content in Architecture
  • Architectural Structure and Design
  • History of Architecture
  • Residential and Domestic Buildings
  • Theory of Architecture
  • Browse content in Art
  • Art Subjects and Themes
  • History of Art
  • Industrial and Commercial Art
  • Theory of Art
  • Biographical Studies
  • Byzantine Studies
  • Browse content in Classical Studies
  • Classical Literature
  • Classical Reception
  • Classical History
  • Classical Philosophy
  • Classical Mythology
  • Classical Art and Architecture
  • Classical Oratory and Rhetoric
  • Greek and Roman Papyrology
  • Greek and Roman Archaeology
  • Greek and Roman Epigraphy
  • Greek and Roman Law
  • Late Antiquity
  • Religion in the Ancient World
  • Digital Humanities
  • Browse content in History
  • Colonialism and Imperialism
  • Diplomatic History
  • Environmental History
  • Genealogy, Heraldry, Names, and Honours
  • Genocide and Ethnic Cleansing
  • Historical Geography
  • History by Period
  • History of Emotions
  • History of Agriculture
  • History of Education
  • History of Gender and Sexuality
  • Industrial History
  • Intellectual History
  • International History
  • Labour History
  • Legal and Constitutional History
  • Local and Family History
  • Maritime History
  • Military History
  • National Liberation and Post-Colonialism
  • Oral History
  • Political History
  • Public History
  • Regional and National History
  • Revolutions and Rebellions
  • Slavery and Abolition of Slavery
  • Social and Cultural History
  • Theory, Methods, and Historiography
  • Urban History
  • World History
  • Browse content in Language Teaching and Learning
  • Language Learning (Specific Skills)
  • Language Teaching Theory and Methods
  • Browse content in Linguistics
  • Applied Linguistics
  • Cognitive Linguistics
  • Computational Linguistics
  • Forensic Linguistics
  • Grammar, Syntax and Morphology
  • Historical and Diachronic Linguistics
  • History of English
  • Language Evolution
  • Language Reference
  • Language Variation
  • Language Families
  • Language Acquisition
  • Lexicography
  • Linguistic Anthropology
  • Linguistic Theories
  • Linguistic Typology
  • Phonetics and Phonology
  • Psycholinguistics
  • Sociolinguistics
  • Translation and Interpretation
  • Writing Systems
  • Browse content in Literature
  • Bibliography
  • Children's Literature Studies
  • Literary Studies (Romanticism)
  • Literary Studies (American)
  • Literary Studies (Modernism)
  • Literary Studies (Asian)
  • Literary Studies (European)
  • Literary Studies (Eco-criticism)
  • Literary Studies - World
  • Literary Studies (1500 to 1800)
  • Literary Studies (19th Century)
  • Literary Studies (20th Century onwards)
  • Literary Studies (African American Literature)
  • Literary Studies (British and Irish)
  • Literary Studies (Early and Medieval)
  • Literary Studies (Fiction, Novelists, and Prose Writers)
  • Literary Studies (Gender Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Graphic Novels)
  • Literary Studies (History of the Book)
  • Literary Studies (Plays and Playwrights)
  • Literary Studies (Poetry and Poets)
  • Literary Studies (Postcolonial Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Queer Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Science Fiction)
  • Literary Studies (Travel Literature)
  • Literary Studies (War Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Women's Writing)
  • Literary Theory and Cultural Studies
  • Mythology and Folklore
  • Shakespeare Studies and Criticism
  • Browse content in Media Studies
  • Browse content in Music
  • Applied Music
  • Dance and Music
  • Ethics in Music
  • Ethnomusicology
  • Gender and Sexuality in Music
  • Medicine and Music
  • Music Cultures
  • Music and Media
  • Music and Culture
  • Music and Religion
  • Music Education and Pedagogy
  • Music Theory and Analysis
  • Musical Scores, Lyrics, and Libretti
  • Musical Structures, Styles, and Techniques
  • Musicology and Music History
  • Performance Practice and Studies
  • Race and Ethnicity in Music
  • Sound Studies
  • Browse content in Performing Arts
  • Browse content in Philosophy
  • Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art
  • Epistemology
  • Feminist Philosophy
  • History of Western Philosophy
  • Metaphysics
  • Moral Philosophy
  • Non-Western Philosophy
  • Philosophy of Language
  • Philosophy of Mind
  • Philosophy of Perception
  • Philosophy of Action
  • Philosophy of Law
  • Philosophy of Religion
  • Philosophy of Science
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic
  • Practical Ethics
  • Social and Political Philosophy
  • Browse content in Religion
  • Biblical Studies
  • Christianity
  • East Asian Religions
  • History of Religion
  • Judaism and Jewish Studies
  • Qumran Studies
  • Religion and Education
  • Religion and Health
  • Religion and Politics
  • Religion and Science
  • Religion and Law
  • Religion and Art, Literature, and Music
  • Religious Studies
  • Browse content in Society and Culture
  • Cookery, Food, and Drink
  • Cultural Studies
  • Customs and Traditions
  • Ethical Issues and Debates
  • Hobbies, Games, Arts and Crafts
  • Lifestyle, Home, and Garden
  • Natural world, Country Life, and Pets
  • Popular Beliefs and Controversial Knowledge
  • Sports and Outdoor Recreation
  • Technology and Society
  • Travel and Holiday
  • Visual Culture
  • Browse content in Law
  • Arbitration
  • Browse content in Company and Commercial Law
  • Commercial Law
  • Company Law
  • Browse content in Comparative Law
  • Systems of Law
  • Competition Law
  • Browse content in Constitutional and Administrative Law
  • Government Powers
  • Judicial Review
  • Local Government Law
  • Military and Defence Law
  • Parliamentary and Legislative Practice
  • Construction Law
  • Contract Law
  • Browse content in Criminal Law
  • Criminal Procedure
  • Criminal Evidence Law
  • Sentencing and Punishment
  • Employment and Labour Law
  • Environment and Energy Law
  • Browse content in Financial Law
  • Banking Law
  • Insolvency Law
  • History of Law
  • Human Rights and Immigration
  • Intellectual Property Law
  • Browse content in International Law
  • Private International Law and Conflict of Laws
  • Public International Law
  • IT and Communications Law
  • Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
  • Law and Society
  • Law and Politics
  • Browse content in Legal System and Practice
  • Courts and Procedure
  • Legal Skills and Practice
  • Primary Sources of Law
  • Regulation of Legal Profession
  • Medical and Healthcare Law
  • Browse content in Policing
  • Criminal Investigation and Detection
  • Police and Security Services
  • Police Procedure and Law
  • Police Regional Planning
  • Browse content in Property Law
  • Personal Property Law
  • Study and Revision
  • Terrorism and National Security Law
  • Browse content in Trusts Law
  • Wills and Probate or Succession
  • Browse content in Medicine and Health
  • Browse content in Allied Health Professions
  • Arts Therapies
  • Clinical Science
  • Dietetics and Nutrition
  • Occupational Therapy
  • Operating Department Practice
  • Physiotherapy
  • Radiography
  • Speech and Language Therapy
  • Browse content in Anaesthetics
  • General Anaesthesia
  • Neuroanaesthesia
  • Clinical Neuroscience
  • Browse content in Clinical Medicine
  • Acute Medicine
  • Cardiovascular Medicine
  • Clinical Genetics
  • Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics
  • Dermatology
  • Endocrinology and Diabetes
  • Gastroenterology
  • Genito-urinary Medicine
  • Geriatric Medicine
  • Infectious Diseases
  • Medical Toxicology
  • Medical Oncology
  • Pain Medicine
  • Palliative Medicine
  • Rehabilitation Medicine
  • Respiratory Medicine and Pulmonology
  • Rheumatology
  • Sleep Medicine
  • Sports and Exercise Medicine
  • Community Medical Services
  • Critical Care
  • Emergency Medicine
  • Forensic Medicine
  • Haematology
  • History of Medicine
  • Browse content in Medical Skills
  • Clinical Skills
  • Communication Skills
  • Nursing Skills
  • Surgical Skills
  • Medical Ethics
  • Browse content in Medical Dentistry
  • Oral and Maxillofacial Surgery
  • Paediatric Dentistry
  • Restorative Dentistry and Orthodontics
  • Surgical Dentistry
  • Medical Statistics and Methodology
  • Browse content in Neurology
  • Clinical Neurophysiology
  • Neuropathology
  • Nursing Studies
  • Browse content in Obstetrics and Gynaecology
  • Gynaecology
  • Occupational Medicine
  • Ophthalmology
  • Otolaryngology (ENT)
  • Browse content in Paediatrics
  • Neonatology
  • Browse content in Pathology
  • Chemical Pathology
  • Clinical Cytogenetics and Molecular Genetics
  • Histopathology
  • Medical Microbiology and Virology
  • Patient Education and Information
  • Browse content in Pharmacology
  • Psychopharmacology
  • Browse content in Popular Health
  • Caring for Others
  • Complementary and Alternative Medicine
  • Self-help and Personal Development
  • Browse content in Preclinical Medicine
  • Cell Biology
  • Molecular Biology and Genetics
  • Reproduction, Growth and Development
  • Primary Care
  • Professional Development in Medicine
  • Browse content in Psychiatry
  • Addiction Medicine
  • Child and Adolescent Psychiatry
  • Forensic Psychiatry
  • Learning Disabilities
  • Old Age Psychiatry
  • Psychotherapy
  • Browse content in Public Health and Epidemiology
  • Epidemiology
  • Public Health
  • Browse content in Radiology
  • Clinical Radiology
  • Interventional Radiology
  • Nuclear Medicine
  • Radiation Oncology
  • Reproductive Medicine
  • Browse content in Surgery
  • Cardiothoracic Surgery
  • Gastro-intestinal and Colorectal Surgery
  • General Surgery
  • Neurosurgery
  • Paediatric Surgery
  • Peri-operative Care
  • Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery
  • Surgical Oncology
  • Transplant Surgery
  • Trauma and Orthopaedic Surgery
  • Vascular Surgery
  • Browse content in Science and Mathematics
  • Browse content in Biological Sciences
  • Aquatic Biology
  • Biochemistry
  • Bioinformatics and Computational Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology and Conservation
  • Evolutionary Biology
  • Genetics and Genomics
  • Microbiology
  • Molecular and Cell Biology
  • Natural History
  • Plant Sciences and Forestry
  • Research Methods in Life Sciences
  • Structural Biology
  • Systems Biology
  • Zoology and Animal Sciences
  • Browse content in Chemistry
  • Analytical Chemistry
  • Computational Chemistry
  • Crystallography
  • Environmental Chemistry
  • Industrial Chemistry
  • Inorganic Chemistry
  • Materials Chemistry
  • Medicinal Chemistry
  • Mineralogy and Gems
  • Organic Chemistry
  • Physical Chemistry
  • Polymer Chemistry
  • Study and Communication Skills in Chemistry
  • Theoretical Chemistry
  • Browse content in Computer Science
  • Artificial Intelligence
  • Computer Architecture and Logic Design
  • Game Studies
  • Human-Computer Interaction
  • Mathematical Theory of Computation
  • Programming Languages
  • Software Engineering
  • Systems Analysis and Design
  • Virtual Reality
  • Browse content in Computing
  • Business Applications
  • Computer Games
  • Computer Security
  • Computer Networking and Communications
  • Digital Lifestyle
  • Graphical and Digital Media Applications
  • Operating Systems
  • Browse content in Earth Sciences and Geography
  • Atmospheric Sciences
  • Environmental Geography
  • Geology and the Lithosphere
  • Maps and Map-making
  • Meteorology and Climatology
  • Oceanography and Hydrology
  • Palaeontology
  • Physical Geography and Topography
  • Regional Geography
  • Soil Science
  • Urban Geography
  • Browse content in Engineering and Technology
  • Agriculture and Farming
  • Biological Engineering
  • Civil Engineering, Surveying, and Building
  • Electronics and Communications Engineering
  • Energy Technology
  • Engineering (General)
  • Environmental Science, Engineering, and Technology
  • History of Engineering and Technology
  • Mechanical Engineering and Materials
  • Technology of Industrial Chemistry
  • Transport Technology and Trades
  • Browse content in Environmental Science
  • Applied Ecology (Environmental Science)
  • Conservation of the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Environmental Sustainability
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Environmental Science)
  • Management of Land and Natural Resources (Environmental Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environmental Science)
  • Nuclear Issues (Environmental Science)
  • Pollution and Threats to the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Environmental Science)
  • History of Science and Technology
  • Browse content in Materials Science
  • Ceramics and Glasses
  • Composite Materials
  • Metals, Alloying, and Corrosion
  • Nanotechnology
  • Browse content in Mathematics
  • Applied Mathematics
  • Biomathematics and Statistics
  • History of Mathematics
  • Mathematical Education
  • Mathematical Finance
  • Mathematical Analysis
  • Numerical and Computational Mathematics
  • Probability and Statistics
  • Pure Mathematics
  • Browse content in Neuroscience
  • Cognition and Behavioural Neuroscience
  • Development of the Nervous System
  • Disorders of the Nervous System
  • History of Neuroscience
  • Invertebrate Neurobiology
  • Molecular and Cellular Systems
  • Neuroendocrinology and Autonomic Nervous System
  • Neuroscientific Techniques
  • Sensory and Motor Systems
  • Browse content in Physics
  • Astronomy and Astrophysics
  • Atomic, Molecular, and Optical Physics
  • Biological and Medical Physics
  • Classical Mechanics
  • Computational Physics
  • Condensed Matter Physics
  • Electromagnetism, Optics, and Acoustics
  • History of Physics
  • Mathematical and Statistical Physics
  • Measurement Science
  • Nuclear Physics
  • Particles and Fields
  • Plasma Physics
  • Quantum Physics
  • Relativity and Gravitation
  • Semiconductor and Mesoscopic Physics
  • Browse content in Psychology
  • Affective Sciences
  • Clinical Psychology
  • Cognitive Psychology
  • Cognitive Neuroscience
  • Criminal and Forensic Psychology
  • Developmental Psychology
  • Educational Psychology
  • Evolutionary Psychology
  • Health Psychology
  • History and Systems in Psychology
  • Music Psychology
  • Neuropsychology
  • Organizational Psychology
  • Psychological Assessment and Testing
  • Psychology of Human-Technology Interaction
  • Psychology Professional Development and Training
  • Research Methods in Psychology
  • Social Psychology
  • Browse content in Social Sciences
  • Browse content in Anthropology
  • Anthropology of Religion
  • Human Evolution
  • Medical Anthropology
  • Physical Anthropology
  • Regional Anthropology
  • Social and Cultural Anthropology
  • Theory and Practice of Anthropology
  • Browse content in Business and Management
  • Business Ethics
  • Business History
  • Business Strategy
  • Business and Technology
  • Business and Government
  • Business and the Environment
  • Comparative Management
  • Corporate Governance
  • Corporate Social Responsibility
  • Entrepreneurship
  • Health Management
  • Human Resource Management
  • Industrial and Employment Relations
  • Industry Studies
  • Information and Communication Technologies
  • International Business
  • Knowledge Management
  • Management and Management Techniques
  • Operations Management
  • Organizational Theory and Behaviour
  • Pensions and Pension Management
  • Public and Nonprofit Management
  • Strategic Management
  • Supply Chain Management
  • Browse content in Criminology and Criminal Justice
  • Criminal Justice
  • Criminology
  • Forms of Crime
  • International and Comparative Criminology
  • Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice
  • Development Studies
  • Browse content in Economics
  • Agricultural, Environmental, and Natural Resource Economics
  • Asian Economics
  • Behavioural Finance
  • Behavioural Economics and Neuroeconomics
  • Econometrics and Mathematical Economics
  • Economic History
  • Economic Methodology
  • Economic Systems
  • Economic Development and Growth
  • Financial Markets
  • Financial Institutions and Services
  • General Economics and Teaching
  • Health, Education, and Welfare
  • History of Economic Thought
  • International Economics
  • Labour and Demographic Economics
  • Law and Economics
  • Macroeconomics and Monetary Economics
  • Microeconomics
  • Public Economics
  • Urban, Rural, and Regional Economics
  • Welfare Economics
  • Browse content in Education
  • Adult Education and Continuous Learning
  • Care and Counselling of Students
  • Early Childhood and Elementary Education
  • Educational Equipment and Technology
  • Educational Strategies and Policy
  • Higher and Further Education
  • Organization and Management of Education
  • Philosophy and Theory of Education
  • Schools Studies
  • Secondary Education
  • Teaching of a Specific Subject
  • Teaching of Specific Groups and Special Educational Needs
  • Teaching Skills and Techniques
  • Browse content in Environment
  • Applied Ecology (Social Science)
  • Climate Change
  • Conservation of the Environment (Social Science)
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Social Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environment)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Social Science)
  • Browse content in Human Geography
  • Cultural Geography
  • Economic Geography
  • Political Geography
  • Browse content in Interdisciplinary Studies
  • Communication Studies
  • Museums, Libraries, and Information Sciences
  • Browse content in Politics
  • African Politics
  • Asian Politics
  • Chinese Politics
  • Comparative Politics
  • Conflict Politics
  • Elections and Electoral Studies
  • Environmental Politics
  • European Union
  • Foreign Policy
  • Gender and Politics
  • Human Rights and Politics
  • Indian Politics
  • International Relations
  • International Organization (Politics)
  • International Political Economy
  • Irish Politics
  • Latin American Politics
  • Middle Eastern Politics
  • Political Behaviour
  • Political Economy
  • Political Institutions
  • Political Theory
  • Political Methodology
  • Political Communication
  • Political Philosophy
  • Political Sociology
  • Politics and Law
  • Public Policy
  • Public Administration
  • Quantitative Political Methodology
  • Regional Political Studies
  • Russian Politics
  • Security Studies
  • State and Local Government
  • UK Politics
  • US Politics
  • Browse content in Regional and Area Studies
  • African Studies
  • Asian Studies
  • East Asian Studies
  • Japanese Studies
  • Latin American Studies
  • Middle Eastern Studies
  • Native American Studies
  • Scottish Studies
  • Browse content in Research and Information
  • Research Methods
  • Browse content in Social Work
  • Addictions and Substance Misuse
  • Adoption and Fostering
  • Care of the Elderly
  • Child and Adolescent Social Work
  • Couple and Family Social Work
  • Developmental and Physical Disabilities Social Work
  • Direct Practice and Clinical Social Work
  • Emergency Services
  • Human Behaviour and the Social Environment
  • International and Global Issues in Social Work
  • Mental and Behavioural Health
  • Social Justice and Human Rights
  • Social Policy and Advocacy
  • Social Work and Crime and Justice
  • Social Work Macro Practice
  • Social Work Practice Settings
  • Social Work Research and Evidence-based Practice
  • Welfare and Benefit Systems
  • Browse content in Sociology
  • Childhood Studies
  • Community Development
  • Comparative and Historical Sociology
  • Economic Sociology
  • Gender and Sexuality
  • Gerontology and Ageing
  • Health, Illness, and Medicine
  • Marriage and the Family
  • Migration Studies
  • Occupations, Professions, and Work
  • Organizations
  • Population and Demography
  • Race and Ethnicity
  • Social Theory
  • Social Movements and Social Change
  • Social Research and Statistics
  • Social Stratification, Inequality, and Mobility
  • Sociology of Religion
  • Sociology of Education
  • Sport and Leisure
  • Urban and Rural Studies
  • Browse content in Warfare and Defence
  • Defence Strategy, Planning, and Research
  • Land Forces and Warfare
  • Military Administration
  • Military Life and Institutions
  • Naval Forces and Warfare
  • Other Warfare and Defence Issues
  • Peace Studies and Conflict Resolution
  • Weapons and Equipment

Representation in Cognitive Science

Representation in Cognitive Science

  • Cite Icon Cite
  • Permissions Icon Permissions

The representational theory of mind (RTM) has given us the powerful insight that thinking consists of the processing of mental representations. Behaviour is the result of these cognitive processes and makes sense in the light of their contents. There is no widely accepted account of how representations get their content – of the metaphysics of representational content. That question, usually asked about representations at the personal level like beliefs and conscious states, is equally pressing for the subpersonal representations that pervade our best explanatory theories in cognitive science. This book argues that well-understood naturalistic resources can be combined to provide an account of subpersonal representational content. It shows how contents arise in a series of detailed case studies in cognitive science. The account is pluralistic, allowing that content is constituted differently in different cases. Building on insights from previous theories, especially teleosemantics, the accounts combine an appeal to correlational information and structural correspondence with an expanded notion of etiological function, which captures the kinds of stabilizing processes that give rise to content. The accounts support a distinction between descriptive and directive content. They also allow us to see how representational explanation gets its distinctive explanatory purchase.

Signed in as

Institutional accounts.

  • Google Scholar Indexing
  • GoogleCrawler [DO NOT DELETE]

Personal account

  • Sign in with email/username & password
  • Get email alerts
  • Save searches
  • Purchase content
  • Activate your purchase/trial code

Institutional access

  • Sign in with a library card Sign in with username/password Recommend to your librarian
  • Institutional account management
  • Get help with access

Access to content on Oxford Academic is often provided through institutional subscriptions and purchases. If you are a member of an institution with an active account, you may be able to access content in one of the following ways:

IP based access

Typically, access is provided across an institutional network to a range of IP addresses. This authentication occurs automatically, and it is not possible to sign out of an IP authenticated account.

Sign in through your institution

Choose this option to get remote access when outside your institution. Shibboleth/Open Athens technology is used to provide single sign-on between your institution’s website and Oxford Academic.

  • Click Sign in through your institution.
  • Select your institution from the list provided, which will take you to your institution's website to sign in.
  • When on the institution site, please use the credentials provided by your institution. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.
  • Following successful sign in, you will be returned to Oxford Academic.

If your institution is not listed or you cannot sign in to your institution’s website, please contact your librarian or administrator.

Sign in with a library card

Enter your library card number to sign in. If you cannot sign in, please contact your librarian.

Society Members

Society member access to a journal is achieved in one of the following ways:

Sign in through society site

Many societies offer single sign-on between the society website and Oxford Academic. If you see ‘Sign in through society site’ in the sign in pane within a journal:

  • Click Sign in through society site.
  • When on the society site, please use the credentials provided by that society. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.

If you do not have a society account or have forgotten your username or password, please contact your society.

Sign in using a personal account

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members. See below.

A personal account can be used to get email alerts, save searches, purchase content, and activate subscriptions.

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members.

Viewing your signed in accounts

Click the account icon in the top right to:

  • View your signed in personal account and access account management features.
  • View the institutional accounts that are providing access.

Signed in but can't access content

Oxford Academic is home to a wide variety of products. The institutional subscription may not cover the content that you are trying to access. If you believe you should have access to that content, please contact your librarian.

For librarians and administrators, your personal account also provides access to institutional account management. Here you will find options to view and activate subscriptions, manage institutional settings and access options, access usage statistics, and more.

Our books are available by subscription or purchase to libraries and institutions.

  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Rights and permissions
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

Visit us today at 314 Main St, Cambridge, MA 02142 Close this alert

The MIT Press Bookstore

What Are Mental Representations? (Philosophy of Mind)

Description.

The topic of this book is mental representation, a theoretical concept that lies at the core of cognitive science. Together with the idea that thinking is analogous to computational processing, this concept is responsible for the "cognitive turn" in the sciences of the mind and brain since the 1950s. Conceiving of cognitive processes (such as perception, reasoning, and motor control) as consisting of the manipulation of contentful vehicles that represent the world has led to tremendous empirical advancements in our explanations of behaviour. Perhaps the most famous discovery that explains behavior by appealing to the notion of mental representations was the discovery of 'place' cells that underlie spatial navigation and positioning, which earned researchers John O'Keefe, May-Britt Moser, and Edvard I. Moser a joint Nobel Prize in 2014. And yet, despite the empirical importance of the concept, there is no agreed definition or theoretical understanding of mental representation. This book constitutes a state-of-the-art overview on the topic of mental representation, assembling some of the leading experts in the field and allowing them to engage in meaningful exchanges over some of the most contentious questions. The collection gathers both proponents and critics of the notion, making room for debates dealing with the theoretical and ontological status of representations, the possibility of formulating a general account of mental representation which would fit our best explanatory practices, and the possibility of delivering such an account in fully naturalistic terms. Some contributors explore the relation between mutually incompatible notions of mental representation, stemming from the different disciplines composing the cognitive sciences (such as neuroscience, psychology, and computer science). Others question the ontological status and explanatory usefulness of the notion. And finally, some try to sketch a general theory of mental representations that could face the challenges outlined in the more critical chapters of the volume.

About the Author

Joulia Smortchkova is a philosopher of cognitive science, working at the University of Oxford as a postdoctoral fellow. She completed her PhD at the Jean Nicod Institute with a thesis on the social contents of perception. She works on social cognition, metacognition, mental representations, types of explanation and natural kinds in psychology. Krzysztof Dolęga is currently a postdoctoral researcher at the Ruhr-Universität Bochum, where he previously completed his PhD under the supervision of Tobias Schlicht and Daniel Dennett. His research interests cluster around topics such as consciousness, mental representation, computational explanation, and models of explanation more generally. Tobias Schlicht is Professor of Philosophy at the Ruhr-Universit] Bochum with an interdisciplinary interest in consciousness and cognition. He wrote two books on the mind-body problem and social cognition and published numerous papers on consciousness, cognition and the foundations of cognitive science.

Other Books in Series

Human Reasoning (Elements in Philosophy of Mind)

Human Reasoning (Elements in Philosophy of Mind)

Personal Identity and the Self (Elements in Philosophy of Mind)

Personal Identity and the Self (Elements in Philosophy of Mind)

Conscious Mind in Search of a Fundamental Theory (Revised) (Philosophy of Mind)

Conscious Mind in Search of a Fundamental Theory (Revised) (Philosophy of Mind)

Combining Minds: How to Think about Composite Subjectivity (Philosophy of Mind)

Combining Minds: How to Think about Composite Subjectivity (Philosophy of Mind)

The Varieties of Consciousness (Philosophy of Mind)

The Varieties of Consciousness (Philosophy of Mind)

The Character of Consciousness (Philosophy of Mind)

The Character of Consciousness (Philosophy of Mind)

Imagination and Creative Thinking (Elements in Philosophy of Mind)

Imagination and Creative Thinking (Elements in Philosophy of Mind)

Mindreading and Social Cognition (Elements in Philosophy of Mind)

Mindreading and Social Cognition (Elements in Philosophy of Mind)

Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension (Philosophy of Mind)

Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension (Philosophy of Mind)

The Contents of Visual Experience (Philosophy of Mind)

The Contents of Visual Experience (Philosophy of Mind)

Perception, Hallucination, and Illusion (Philosophy of Mind)

Perception, Hallucination, and Illusion (Philosophy of Mind)

Consciousness and Quantum Mechanics (Philosophy of Mind)

Consciousness and Quantum Mechanics (Philosophy of Mind)

The Computational Theory of Mind (Elements in Philosophy of Mind)

The Computational Theory of Mind (Elements in Philosophy of Mind)

Non-Physicalist Theories of Consciousness (Elements in Philosophy of Mind)

Non-Physicalist Theories of Consciousness (Elements in Philosophy of Mind)

Cognitive Systems and the Extended Mind (Philosophy of Mind)

Cognitive Systems and the Extended Mind (Philosophy of Mind)

Thinking Without Words (Philosophy of Mind)

Thinking Without Words (Philosophy of Mind)

Robert Grosseteste and the Pursuit of Religious and Scientific Learning in the Middle Ages (Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind #18)

Robert Grosseteste and the Pursuit of Religious and Scientific Learning in the Middle Ages (Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind #18)

You may also like.

Real Hallucinations: Psychiatric Illness, Intentionality, and the Interpersonal World (Philosophical Psychopathology)

Real Hallucinations: Psychiatric Illness, Intentionality, and the Interpersonal World (Philosophical Psychopathology)

Responsible Brains: Neuroscience, Law, and Human Culpability

Responsible Brains: Neuroscience, Law, and Human Culpability

The Real Work: On the Mystery of Mastery

The Real Work: On the Mystery of Mastery

How to Think Like a Philosopher: Scholars, Dreamers and Sages Who Can Teach Us How to Live

How to Think Like a Philosopher: Scholars, Dreamers and Sages Who Can Teach Us How to Live

Then I Am Myself the World: What Consciousness Is and How to Expand It

Then I Am Myself the World: What Consciousness Is and How to Expand It

Amphibious Soul: Finding the Wild in a Tame World

Amphibious Soul: Finding the Wild in a Tame World

Just in Time: Temporality, Aesthetic Experience, and Cognitive Neuroscience

Just in Time: Temporality, Aesthetic Experience, and Cognitive Neuroscience

Erotism: Death and Sensuality

Erotism: Death and Sensuality

The Handbook of Rationality

The Handbook of Rationality

Open Minded: Searching for Truth about the Unconscious Mind

Open Minded: Searching for Truth about the Unconscious Mind

Lessons from an American Stoic: How Emerson Can Change Your Life

Lessons from an American Stoic: How Emerson Can Change Your Life

Mind Design III: Philosophy, Psychology, and Artificial Intelligence

Mind Design III: Philosophy, Psychology, and Artificial Intelligence

Lacan: Anti-Philosophy 3 (Seminars of Alain Badiou)

Lacan: Anti-Philosophy 3 (Seminars of Alain Badiou)

101 Clues to a Happy Life

101 Clues to a Happy Life

Begin Again: How We Got Here and Where We Might Go - Our Human Story. So Far.

Begin Again: How We Got Here and Where We Might Go - Our Human Story. So Far.

Scenes of Attention: Essays on Mind, Time, and the Senses

Scenes of Attention: Essays on Mind, Time, and the Senses

Braintrust: What Neuroscience Tells Us about Morality (Princeton Science Library #57)

Braintrust: What Neuroscience Tells Us about Morality (Princeton Science Library #57)

Out of the Cave: A Natural Philosophy of Mind and Knowing

Out of the Cave: A Natural Philosophy of Mind and Knowing

The Social Turn in Moral Psychology

The Social Turn in Moral Psychology

How to Tell a Joke: An Ancient Guide to the Art of Humor (Ancient Wisdom for Modern Readers)

How to Tell a Joke: An Ancient Guide to the Art of Humor (Ancient Wisdom for Modern Readers)

Enlightened Self-Interest: Individualism, Community, and the Common Good

Enlightened Self-Interest: Individualism, Community, and the Common Good

Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance [50th Anniversary Edition]: An Inquiry into Values

Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance [50th Anniversary Edition]: An Inquiry into Values

Philosophy and Psychedelics: Frameworks for Exceptional Experience

Philosophy and Psychedelics: Frameworks for Exceptional Experience

Blockheads!: Essays on Ned Block's Philosophy of Mind and Consciousness

Blockheads!: Essays on Ned Block's Philosophy of Mind and Consciousness

The Theory of Everything Else: A Voyage Into the World of the Weird

The Theory of Everything Else: A Voyage Into the World of the Weird

The Chinese Pleasure Book

The Chinese Pleasure Book

On the Couch: Writers Analyze Sigmund Freud

On the Couch: Writers Analyze Sigmund Freud

A User's Guide to Melancholy

A User's Guide to Melancholy

Sign up to receive our newsletter.

News and information from Kendall Square's underground bookstore

Search Icon

Events See all →

At-home anthro live.

Penn Museum exterior

1:00 p.m. - 1:45 p.m.

Alumni Weekend 2024

penn alumni waving pennants at the parade

Various locations

268th Commencement

University of Pennsylvania flag.

Franklin Field

Wawa Welcome America Day

10:00 a.m. - 5:00 p.m.

Penn Museum, 3260 South St.

Science & Technology

Defining neural ‘representation’

Neuroscientists frequently say that neural activity ‘represents’ certain phenomena. pik professor konrad kording and postdoc ben baker led a study that took a philosophical approach to tease out what the term means..

A computer screen displays the brain activity of a man with electrodes on his head.

One of neuroscience’s greatest challenges is to bridge the gaps between the external environment, the brain’s internal electrical activity, and the abstract workings of behavior and cognition. Many neuroscientists rely on the word “representation” to connect these phenomena: A burst of neural activity in the visual cortex may represent the face of a friend or neurons in the brain’s memory centers may represent a childhood memory.

But with the many complex relationships between mind, brain, and environment, it’s not always clear what neuroscientists mean when they say neural activity “represents” something. Lack of clarity around this concept can lead to miscommunication, flawed conclusions, and unnecessary disagreements.

To tackle this issue, an interdisciplinary paper takes a philosophical approach to delineating the many aspects of the word “representation” in neuroscience. The work, published in Trends in Cognitive Sciences , comes from the lab of Konrad Kording , a Penn Integrates Knowledge University Professor and senior author on the study whose research lies at the intersection of neuroscience and machine learning.

“The term ‘representation’ is probably one of the most common words in all of neuroscience,” says Kording, who has appointments in the Perelman School of Medicine and School of Engineering and Applied Science . “But it might mean something very different from one professor to another.”

It’s also a term that is “philosophically loaded,” says Ben Baker , lead study author and a postdoctoral researcher in Kording’s lab . Discourse on mental representation dates back as far as Aristotle, he says, and those early discussions laid the groundwork for modern cognitive science. However, as neuroscientists adopted the term, its evolving definition was never fully fleshed out.

Using his background in philosophy of mind and philosophy of science, Baker conducted a literature review, analyzing foundational experiments and major themes in neuroscience to determine how researchers applied the term “representation.” He and his coauthors compared these usages to the term’s function in philosophy and identified three aspects to the use of the word in neuroscience, each of which builds from the previous one.

The first, most straightforward aspect is correlational, in which a neural state correlates with an event or feature of the environment. For example, a researcher may find that a group of neurons fires whenever a mouse sees a predator. Because that particular neural state is correlated to seeing the predator, the researcher may say the neural state represents the predator.

In the past, technology limited early neuroscientists primarily to recording neural activity, rather than inducing or modeling it. These experiments produced mostly correlative conclusions, which shaped neuroscientists’ early concept of representation, according to Kording and Baker.

But those who hope to build comprehensive models of behavior are interested in more than just correlation; they want to know how neural activity causes behavior related to a particular event or feature. The second aspect of representation that Baker and Kording identified also includes a causal component. When researchers use the term in this sense, they mean that neural activity related to some event or feature causes behavior related to that event or feature. Building off the previous example, if a mouse’s neural state represents seeing a predator, then that neural state may cause an action such as hiding or running away.

This definition is more common in contemporary neuroscience studies. Modern experimental techniques such as optogenetics allow for precise stimulation of specific populations of neurons, making it easier for scientists to prove causal links between neural activity and behavior.

Beyond what behaviors a neural state may cause, many neuroscientists also want to know why animals behave that way. The third aspect of representation encompasses this idea by adding a teleological component, which emphasizes an action’s purpose rather than its cause.

In this usage, there is a reason the neural state and its corresponding behavior correlate with an event or feature. Returning to the mouse example, the neural activity that represents seeing a predator and causes the mouse to run away exists so the mouse will survive. That’s its purpose .

Teleology is more often discussed in philosophy than in neuroscience, but neuroscientists’ reasoning often implies teleology, according to Kording and Baker. Teleological definitions of representation are especially common in neuroscience research that tries to model abstract components of cognitive tasks. Many evolutionary explanations of behavior rely on teleological reasoning as well.

The researchers say they hope their paper will help tamp down ambiguous use of the word “representation” and promote more rigorous discourse in the field. “The end goal is clear communication,” Baker says. Once that happens, Kording adds, “there's many different discussions you can have.”

Konrad Kording is a Penn Integrates Knowledge University Professor with joint appointments in the Department of Neuroscience the Perelman School of Medicine and in the Department of Bioengineering in the School of Engineering and Applied Science .

Ben Baker is a postdoctoral researcher in the Kording lab and a Provost Postdoctoral Fellow . Baker received his Ph.D. in philosophy from Penn.

Also coauthor on the paper is Benjamin Lansdell , a data scientist in the Department of Developmental Neurobiology at St. Jude Children’s Hospital and former postdoctoral researcher in the Kording lab.

Funding for this study came from the National Institutes of Health (awards 1-R01-EB028162-01 and R01EY021579) and the University of Pennsylvania Office of the Vice Provost for Research.

Class of 2025 relishes time together at Hey Day

students working with clay slabs at a table

Arts, Humanities, & Social Sciences

Picturing artistic pursuits

Hundreds of undergraduates take classes in the fine arts each semester, among them painting and drawing, ceramics and sculpture, printmaking and animation, photography and videography. The courses, through the School of Arts & Sciences and the Stuart Weitzman School of Design, give students the opportunity to immerse themselves in an art form in a collaborative way.

interim president larry jameson at solar panel ribbon cutting

Campus & Community

Penn celebrates operation and benefits of largest solar power project in Pennsylvania

Solar production has begun at the Great Cove I and II facilities in central Pennsylvania, the equivalent of powering 70% of the electricity demand from Penn’s academic campus and health system in the Philadelphia area.

elementary age students with teacher

Education, Business, & Law

Investing in future teachers and educational leaders

The Empowerment Through Education Scholarship Program at Penn’s Graduate School of Education is helping to prepare and retain teachers and educational leaders.

barbara earl thomas with seth parker woods

‘The Illuminated Body’ fuses color, light, and sound

A new Arthur Ross Gallery exhibition of work by artist Barbara Earl Thomas features cut-paper portraits reminiscent of stained glass and an immersive installation constructed with intricately cut material lit from behind.

Logo Oapen

  • For Librarians
  • For Publishers
  • For Researchers
  •   OAPEN Home

Representation in Cognitive Science

Thumbnail

Publisher website

Publication date and place.

  • H2020 European Research Council - 681422 - MetCogCon Research grant information Find all documents

Classification

  • Imported or submitted locally

Export search results

The export option will allow you to export the current search results of the entered query to a file. Differen formats are available for download. To export the items, click on the button corresponding with the preferred download format.

A logged-in user can export up to 15000 items. If you're not logged in, you can export no more than 500 items.

To select a subset of the search results, click "Selective Export" button and make a selection of the items you want to export. The amount of items that can be exported at once is similarly restricted as the full export.

After making a selection, click one of the export format buttons. The amount of items that will be exported is indicated in the bubble next to export format.

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Mental representation.

The notion of a "mental representation" is, arguably, in the first instance a theoretical construct of cognitive science. As such, it is a basic concept of the Computational Theory of Mind, according to which cognitive states and processes are constituted by the occurrence, transformation and storage (in the mind/brain) of information-bearing structures (representations) of one kind or another.

However, on the assumption that a representation is an object with semantic properties (content, reference, truth-conditions, truth-value, etc.), a mental representation may be more broadly construed as a mental object with semantic properties. As such, mental representations (and the states and processes that involve them) need not be understood only in computational terms. On this broader construal, mental representation is a philosophical topic with roots in antiquity and a rich history and literature predating the recent "cognitive revolution." Though most contemporary philosophers of mind acknowledge the relevance and importance of cognitive science, they vary in their degree of engagement with its literature, methods and results; and there remain, for many, issues concerning the representational properties of the mind that can be addressed independently of the computational hypothesis.

Though the term ‘Representational Theory of Mind’ is sometimes used almost interchangeably with ‘Computational Theory of Mind’, I will use it here to refer to any theory that postulates the existence of semantically evaluable mental objects, including philosophy's stock in trade mentalia — thoughts, concepts, percepts, ideas, impressions, notions, rules, schemas, images, phantasms, etc. — as well as the various sorts of "subpersonal" representations postulated by cognitive science. Representational theories may thus be contrasted with theories, such as those of Baker (1995), Collins (1987), Dennett (1987), Gibson (1966, 1979), Reid (1764/1997), Stich (1983) and Thau (2002), which deny the existence of such things.

1. The Representational Theory of Mind

2. propositional attitudes.

  • 3. Conceptual and Nonconceptual Representation

4. Representationalism and Phenomenalism

6. content determination, 7. internalism and externalism, 8. the computational theory of mind, 9. thought and language, bibliography, other internet resources, related entries.

The Representational Theory of Mind (RTM) (which goes back at least to Aristotle) takes as its starting point commonsense mental states, such as thoughts, beliefs, desires, perceptions and images. Such states are said to have "intentionality" — they are about or refer to things, and may be evaluated with respect to properties like consistency, truth, appropriateness and accuracy. (For example, the thought that cousins are not related is inconsistent, the belief that Elvis is dead is true, the desire to eat the moon is inappropriate, a visual experience of a ripe strawberry as red is accurate, an image of George W. Bush with dreadlocks is inaccurate.)

RTM defines such intentional mental states as relations to mental representations, and explains the intentionality of the former in terms of the semantic properties of the latter. For example, to believe that Elvis is dead is to be appropriately related to a mental representation whose propositional content is that Elvis is dead . (The desire that Elvis be dead, the fear that he is dead, the regret that he is dead, etc., involve different relations to the same mental representation.) To perceive a strawberry is to have a sensory experience of some kind which is appropriately related to (e.g., caused by) the strawberry.

RTM also understands mental processes such as thinking, reasoning and imagining as sequences of intentional mental states. For example, to imagine the moon rising over a mountain is to entertain a series of mental images of the moon (and a mountain). To infer a proposition q from the propositions p and if p then q is (among other things) to have a sequence of thoughts of the form p , if p then q , q .

Contemporary philosophers of mind have typically supposed (or at least hoped ) that the mind can be naturalized — i.e., that all mental facts have explanations in the terms of natural science. This assumption is shared within cognitive science, which attempts to provide accounts of mental states and processes in terms (ultimately) of features of the brain and central nervous system. In the course of doing so, the various sub-disciplines of cognitive science (including cognitive and computational psychology and cognitive and computational neuroscience) postulate a number of different kinds of structures and processes, many of which are not directly implicated by mental states and processes as commonsensically conceived. There remains, however, a shared commitment to the idea that mental states and processes are to be explained in terms of mental representations.

In philosophy, recent debates about mental representation have centered around the existence of propositional attitudes (beliefs, desires, etc.) and the determination of their contents (how they come to be about what they are about), and the existence of phenomenal properties and their relation to the content of thought and perceptual experience. Within cognitive science itself, the philosophically relevant debates have been focused on the computational architecture of the brain and central nervous system, and the compatibility of scientific and commonsense accounts of mentality.

Intentional Realists such as Dretske (e.g., 1988) and Fodor (e.g., 1987) note that the generalizations we apply in everyday life in predicting and explaining each other's behavior (often collectively referred to as "folk psychology") are both remarkably successful and indispensable. What a person believes, doubts, desires, fears, etc. is a highly reliable indicator of what that person will do; and we have no other way of making sense of each other's behavior than by ascribing such states and applying the relevant generalizations. We are thus committed to the basic truth of commonsense psychology and, hence, to the existence of the states its generalizations refer to. (Some realists, such as Fodor, also hold that commonsense psychology will be vindicated by cognitive science, given that propositional attitudes can be construed as computational relations to mental representations.)

Intentional Eliminativists , such as Churchland, (perhaps) Dennett and (at one time) Stich argue that no such things as propositional attitudes (and their constituent representational states) are implicated by the successful explanation and prediction of our mental lives and behavior. Churchland denies that the generalizations of commonsense propositional-attitude psychology are true. He (1981) argues that folk psychology is a theory of the mind with a long history of failure and decline, and that it resists incorporation into the framework of modern scientific theories (including cognitive psychology). As such, it is comparable to alchemy and phlogiston theory, and ought to suffer a comparable fate. Commonsense psychology is false , and the states (and representations) it postulates simply don't exist. (It should be noted that Churchland is not an eliminativist about mental representation tout court . See, e.g., Churchland 1989.)

Dennett (1987a) grants that the generalizations of commonsense psychology are true and indispensable, but denies that this is sufficient reason to believe in the entities they appear to refer to. He argues that to give an intentional explanation of a system's behavior is merely to adopt the "intentional stance" toward it. If the strategy of assigning contentful states to a system and predicting and explaining its behavior (on the assumption that it is rational — i.e., that it behaves as it should, given the propositional attitudes it should have in its environment) is successful, then the system is intentional, and the propositional-attitude generalizations we apply to it are true. But there is nothing more to having a propositional attitude than this. (See Dennett 1987a: 29.)

Though he has been taken to be thus claiming that intentional explanations should be construed instrumentally, Dennett (1991) insists that he is a "moderate" realist about propositional attitudes, since he believes that the patterns in the behavior and behavioral dispositions of a system on the basis of which we (truly) attribute intentional states to it are objectively real. In the event that there are two or more explanatorily adequate but substantially different systems of intentional ascriptions to an individual, however, Dennett claims there is no fact of the matter about what the system believes (1987b, 1991). This does suggest an irrealism at least with respect to the sorts of things Fodor and Dretske take beliefs to be; though it is not the view that there is simply nothing in the world that makes intentional explanations true.

(Davidson 1973, 1974 and Lewis 1974 also defend the view that what it is to have a propositional attitude is just to be interpretable in a particular way. It is, however, not entirely clear whether they intend their views to imply irrealism about propositional attitudes.)

Stich (1983) argues that cognitive psychology does not (or, in any case, should not) taxonomize mental states by their semantic properties at all, since attribution of psychological states by content is sensitive to factors that render it problematic in the context of a scientific psychology. Cognitive psychology seeks causal explanations of behavior and cognition, and the causal powers of a mental state are determined by its intrinsic "structural" or "syntactic" properties. The semantic properties of a mental state, however, are determined by its extrinsic properties — e.g., its history, environmental or intramental relations. Hence, such properties cannot figure in causal-scientific explanations of behavior. (Fodor 1994 and Dretske 1988 are realist attempts to come to grips with some of these problems.) Stich proposes a syntactic theory of the mind, on which the semantic properties of mental states play no explanatory role. (Stich has changed his views on a number of these issues. See Stich 1996.)

3. Conceptual and Non-Conceptual Representation

It is a traditional assumption among realists about mental representations that representational states come in two basic varieties (cf. Boghossian 1995). There are those, such as thoughts, which are composed of concepts and have no phenomenal ("what-it's-like") features ("qualia"), and those, such as sensory experiences, which have phenomenal features but no conceptual constituents. (Nonconceptual content is usually defined as a kind of content that states of a creature lacking concepts might nonetheless enjoy. [ 1 ] On this taxonomy, mental states can represent either in a way analogous to expressions of natural languages or in a way analogous to drawings, paintings, maps or photographs. (Perceptual states such as seeing that something is blue, are sometimes thought of as hybrid states, consisting of, for example, a non-conceptual sensory experience and a thought, or some more integrated compound of sensory and conceptual components.)

Some historical discussions of the representational properties of mind (e.g., Aristotle 1984, Locke 1689/1975, Hume 1739/1978) seem to assume that nonconceptual representations — percepts ("impressions"), images ("ideas") and the like — are the only kinds of mental representations, and that the mind represents the world in virtue of being in states that resemble things in it. On such a view, all representational states have their content in virtue of their phenomenal features. Powerful arguments, however, focusing on the lack of generality (Berkeley 1975), ambiguity (Wittgenstein 1953) and non-compositionality (Fodor 1981c) of sensory and imagistic representations, as well as their unsuitability to function as logical (Frege 1918/1997, Geach 1957) or mathematical (Frege 1884/1953) concepts, and the symmetry of resemblance (Goodman 1976), convinced philosophers that no theory of mind can get by with only nonconceptual representations construed in this way.

Contemporary disagreement over nonconceptual representation concerns the existence and nature of phenomenal properties and the role they play in determining the content of sensory experience. Dennett (1988), for example, denies that there are such things as qualia at all; while Brandom (2002), McDowell (1994), Rey (1991) and Sellars (1956) deny that they are needed to explain the content of sensory experience. Among those who accept that experiences have phenomenal content, some (Dretske, Lycan, Tye) argue that it is reducible to a kind of intentional content, while others (Block, Loar, Peacocke) argue that it is irreducible. (See the discussion in the next section.)

There has also been dissent from the traditional claim that conceptual representations (thoughts, beliefs) lack phenomenology. Chalmers (1996), Flanagan (1992), Goldman (1993), Horgan and Tiensen (2003), Jackendoff (1987), Levine (1993, 1995, 2001), McGinn (1991a), Pitt (2004), Searle (1992), Siewert (1998) and Strawson (1994), claim that purely symbolic (conscious) representational states themselves have a (perhaps proprietary) phenomenology. If this claim is correct, the question of what role phenomenology plays in the determination of content rearises for conceptual representation; and the eliminativist ambitions of Sellars, Brandom, Rey, et al. would meet a new obstacle. (It would also raise prima face problems for reductivist representationalism (see the next section).)

Among realists about phenomenal properties, the central division is between representationalists (also called "representationists" and "intentionalists") — e.g., Dretske (1995), Harman (1990), Leeds (1993), Lycan (1987, 1996), Rey (1991), Thau (2002), Tye (1995, 2000) — and phenomenalists (also called "phenomenists" and "qualia freaks") — e.g., Block (1996, 2003), Chalmers (1996, forthcoming), Evans (1982), Loar (2003a, 2003b), Peacocke (1983, 1989, 1992, 2001), Raffman (1995), Shoemaker (1990). Representationalists claim that the phenomenal character of a mental state is reducible to a kind of intentional content. Phenomenalists claim that the phenomenal character of a mental state is not so reducible.

The representationalist thesis is often formulated as the claim that phenomenal properties are representational or intentional. However, this formulation is ambiguous between a reductive and a non-reductive claim (though the term ‘representationalism’ is most often used for the reductive claim). (See Chalmers forthcoming.) On one hand, it could mean that the phenomenal content of an experience is a kind of intentional content (the properties it represents). On the other, it could mean that the (irreducible) phenomenal properties of an experience determine an intentional content. Representationalists such as Dretske, Lycan and Tye would assent to the former claim, whereas phenomenalists such as Block, Chalmers, Loar and Peacocke would assent to the latter. (Among phenomenalists, there is further disagreement about whether qualia are intrinsically representational (Loar) or not (Block, Peacocke).

Most (reductive) representationalists are motivated by the conviction that one or another naturalistic explanation of intentionality (see the next section) is, in broad outline, correct, and by the desire to complete the naturalization of the mental by applying such theories to the problem of phenomenality. (Needless to say, most phenomenalists (Chalmers is the major exception) are just as eager to naturalize the phenomenal — though not in the same way.)

The main argument for representationalism appeals to the transparency of experience (cf. Tye 2000: 45-51). The properties that characterize what it's like to have a perceptual experience are presented in experience as properties of objects perceived: in attending to an experience, one seems to "see through it" to the objects and properties it is experiences of . [ 2 ] They are not presented as properties of the experience itself. If nonetheless they were properties of the experience, perception would be massively deceptive. But perception is not massively deceptive. According to the representationalist, the phenomenal character of an experience is due to its representing objective, non-experiential properties. (In veridical perception, these properties are locally instantiated; in illusion and hallucination, they are not.) On this view, introspection is indirect perception: one comes to know what phenomenal features one's experience has by coming to know what objective features it represents.

In order to account for the intuitive differences between conceptual and sensory representations, representationalists appeal to their structural or functional differences. Dretske (1995), for example, distinguishes experiences and thoughts on the basis of the origin and nature of their functions: an experience of a property P is a state of a system whose evolved function is to indicate the presence of P in the environment; a thought representing the property P , on the other hand, is a state of a system whose assigned (learned) function is to calibrate the output of the experiential system. Rey (1991) takes both thoughts and experiences to be relations to sentences in the language of thought, and distinguishes them on the basis of (the functional roles of) such sentences' constituent predicates. Lycan (1987, 1996) distinguishes them in terms of their functional-computational profiles. Tye (2000) distinguishes them in terms of their functional roles and the intrinsic structure of their vehicles: thoughts are representations in a language-like medium, whereas experiences are image-like representations consisting of "symbol-filled arrays." (Cf. the account of mental images in Tye 1991.)

Phenomenalists tend to make use of the same sorts of features (function, intrinsic structure) in explaining some of the intuitive differences between thoughts and experiences; but they do not suppose that such features exhaust the differences between phenomenal and non-phenomenal representations. For the phenomenalist, it is the phenomenal properties of experiences — qualia themselves — that constitute the fundamental difference between experience and thought. Peacocke (1992), for example, develops the notion of a perceptual "scenario" (an assignment of phenomenal properties to coordinates of a three-dimensional egocentric space), whose content is "correct" (a semantic property) if in the corresponding "scene" (the portion of the external world represented by the scenario) properties are distributed as their phenomenal analogues are in the scenario.

Another sort of representation championed by phenomenalists (e.g., Block, Chalmers (2003) and Loar (1996)) is the "phenomenal concept" — a conceptual/phenomenal hybrid consisting of a phenomenological "sample" (an image or an occurrent sensation) integrated with (or functioning as) a conceptual component. Phenomenal concepts are postulated to account for the apparent fact (among others) that, as McGinn (1991b) puts it, "you cannot form [introspective] concepts of conscious properties unless you yourself instantiate those properties." One cannot have a phenomenal concept of a phenomenal property P , and, hence, phenomenal beliefs about P , without having experience of P , because P itself is (in some way) constitutive of the concept of P . (Cf. Jackson 1982, 1986 and Nagel 1974.)

Though imagery has played an important role in the history of philosophy of mind, the important contemporary literature on it is primarily psychological. In a series of psychological experiments done in the 1970s (summarized in Kosslyn 1980 and Shepard and Cooper 1982), subjects' response time in tasks involving mental manipulation and examination of presented figures was found to vary in proportion to the spatial properties (size, orientation, etc.) of the figures presented. The question of how these experimental results are to be explained has kindled a lively debate on the nature of imagery and imagination.

Kosslyn (1980) claims that the results suggest that the tasks were accomplished via the examination and manipulation of mental representations that themselves have spatial properties — i.e., pictorial representations, or images . Others, principally Pylyshyn (1979, 1981a, 1981b, 2003), argue that the empirical facts can be explained in terms exclusively of discursive , or propositional representations and cognitive processes defined over them. (Pylyshyn takes such representations to be sentences in a language of thought.)

The idea that pictorial representations are literally pictures in the head is not taken seriously by proponents of the pictorial view of imagery (see, e.g., Kosslyn and Pomerantz 1977). The claim is, rather, that mental images represent in a way that is relevantly like the way pictures represent. (Attention has been focused on visual imagery — hence the designation ‘pictorial’; though of course there may imagery in other modalities — auditory, olfactory, etc. — as well.)

The distinction between pictorial and discursive representation can be characterized in terms of the distinction between analog and digital representation (Goodman 1976). This distinction has itself been variously understood (Fodor & Pylyshyn 1981, Goodman 1976, Haugeland 1981, Lewis 1971, McGinn 1989), though a widely accepted construal is that analog representation is continuous (i.e., in virtue of continuously variable properties of the representation), while digital representation is discrete (i.e., in virtue of properties a representation either has or doesn't have) (Dretske 1981). (An analog/digital distinction may also be made with respect to cognitive processes . (Block 1983.)) On this understanding of the analog/digital distinction, imagistic representations, which represent in virtue of properties that may vary continuously (such as being more or less bright, loud, vivid, etc.), would be analog, while conceptual representations, whose properties do not vary continuously (a thought cannot be more or less about Elvis: either it is or it is not) would be digital.

It might be supposed that the pictorial/discursive distinction is best made in terms of the phenomenal/nonphenomenal distinction, but it is not obvious that this is the case. For one thing, there may be nonphenomenal properties of representations that vary continuously. Moreover, there are ways of understanding pictorial representation that presuppose neither phenomenality nor analogicity. According to Kosslyn (1980, 1982, 1983), a mental representation is "quasi-pictorial" when every part of the representation corresponds to a part of the object represented, and relative distances between parts of the object represented are preserved among the parts of the representation. But distances between parts of a representation can be defined functionally rather than spatially — for example, in terms of the number of discrete computational steps required to combine stored information about them. (Cf. Rey 1981.)

Tye (1991) proposes a view of images on which they are hybrid representations, consisting both of pictorial and discursive elements. On Tye's account, images are "(labeled) interpreted symbol-filled arrays." The symbols represent discursively, while their arrangement in arrays has representational significance (the location of each "cell" in the array represents a specific viewer-centered 2-D location on the surface of the imagined object).

The contents of mental representations are typically taken to be abstract objects (properties, relations, propositions, sets, etc.). A pressing question, especially for the naturalist, is how mental representations come to have their contents. Here the issue is not how to naturalize content (abstract objects can't be naturalized), but, rather, how to provide a naturalistic account of the content-determining relations between mental representations and the abstract objects they express. There are two basic types of contemporary naturalistic theories of content-determination, causal-informational and functional . [ 3 ]

Causal-informational theories (Dretske 1981, 1988, 1995) hold that the content of a mental representation is grounded in the information it carries about what does (Devitt 1996) or would (Fodor 1987, 1990a) cause it to occur. [ 4 ] There is, however, widespread agreement that causal-informational relations are not sufficient to determine the content of mental representations. Such relations are common, but representation is not. Tree trunks, smoke, thermostats and ringing telephones carry information about what they are causally related to, but they do not represent (in the relevant sense) what they carry information about. Further, a representation can be caused by something it does not represent, and can represent something that has not caused it.

The main attempts to specify what makes a causal-informational state a mental representation are Asymmetric Dependency Theories (e.g., Fodor 1987, 1990a, 1994) and Teleological Theories (Fodor 1990b, Millikan 1984, Papineau 1987, Dretske 1988, 1995). The Asymmetric Dependency Theory distinguishes merely informational relations from representational relations on the basis of their higher-order relations to each other: informational relations depend upon representational relations, but not vice-versa. For example, if tokens of a mental state type are reliably caused by horses, cows-on-dark-nights, zebras-in-the-mist and Great Danes, then they carry information about horses, etc. If, however, such tokens are caused by cows-on-dark-nights, etc. because they were caused by horses, but not vice versa, then they represent horses (or the property horse ).

According to Teleological Theories, representational relations are those a representation-producing mechanism has the selected (by evolution or learning) function of establishing. For example, zebra-caused horse-representations do not mean zebra , because the mechanism by which such tokens are produced has the selected function of indicating horses, not zebras. The horse-representation-producing mechanism that responds to zebras is malfunctioning .

Functional theories (Block 1986, Harman 1973), hold that the content of a mental representation is grounded in its (causal computational, inferential) relations to other mental representations. They differ on whether relata should include all other mental representations or only some of them, and on whether to include external states of affairs. The view that the content of a mental representation is determined by its inferential/computational relations with all other representations is holism ; the view it is determined by relations to only some other mental states is localism (or molecularism ). (The view that the content of a mental state depends on none of its relations to other mental states is atomism .) Functional theories that recognize no content-determining external relata have been called solipsistic (Harman 1987). Some theorists posit distinct roles for internal and external connections, the former determining semantic properties analogous to sense, the latter determining semantic properties analogous to reference (McGinn 1982, Sterelny 1989).

(Reductive) representationalists (Dretske, Lycan, Tye) usually take one or another of these theories to provide an explanation of the (non-conceptual) content of experiential states. They thus tend to be externalists (see the next section) about phenomenological as well as conceptual content. Phenomenalists and non-reductive representationalists (Block, Chalmers, Loar, Peacocke, Siewert), on the other hand, take it that the representational content of such states is (at least in part) determined by their intrinsic phenomenal properties. Further, those who advocate a phenomenology-based approach to conceptual content (Horgan and Tiensen, Loar, Pitt, Searle, Siewert) also seem to be committed to internalist individuation of the content (if not the reference) of such states.

Generally, those who, like informational theorists, think relations to one's (natural or social) environment are (at least partially) determinative of the content of mental representations are externalists (e.g., Burge 1979, 1986b, McGinn 1977, Putnam 1975), whereas those who, like some proponents of functional theories, think representational content is determined by an individual's intrinsic properties alone, are internalists (or individualists ; cf. Putnam 1975, Fodor 1981b).

This issue is widely taken to be of central importance, since psychological explanation, whether commonsense or scientific, is supposed to be both causal and content-based. (Beliefs and desires cause the behaviors they do because they have the contents they do. For example, the desire that one have a beer and the beliefs that there is beer in the refrigerator and that the refrigerator is in the kitchen may explain one's getting up and going to the kitchen.) If, however, a mental representation's having a particular content is due to factors extrinsic to it, it is unclear how its having that content could determine its causal powers, which, arguably, must be intrinsic (see Stich 1983, Fodor 1982, 1987, 1994). Some who accept the standard arguments for externalism have argued that internal factors determine a component of the content of a mental representation. They say that mental representations have both "narrow" content (determined by intrinsic factors) and "wide" or "broad" content (determined by narrow content plus extrinsic factors). (This distinction may be applied to the sub-personal representations of cognitive science as well as to those of commonsense psychology. See von Eckardt 1993: 189.)

Narrow content has been variously construed. Putnam (1975), Fodor (1982: 114; 1994: 39ff), and Block (1986: 627ff), for example, seem to understand it as something like de dicto content (i.e., Fregean sense , or perhaps character , à la Kaplan 1989). On this construal, narrow content is context-independent and directly expressible. Fodor (1987) and Block (1986), however, have also characterized narrow content as radically inexpressible . On this construal, narrow content is a kind of proto-content, or content-determinant, and can be specified only indirectly, via specifications of context/wide-content pairings. On both construals, narrow contents are characterized as functions from context to (wide) content. The narrow content of a representation is determined by properties intrinsic to it or its possessor such as its syntactic structure or its intramental computational or inferential role (or its phenomenology — see, e.g., Searle 1992, Siewert 1998, Pitt forthcoming).

Burge (1986b) has argued that causation-based worries about externalist individuation of psychological content, and the introduction of the narrow notion, are misguided. Fodor (1994, 1998) has more recently urged that a scientific psychology might not need narrow content in order to supply naturalistic (causal) explanations of human cognition and action, since the sorts of cases they were introduced to handle, viz., Twin-Earth cases and Frege cases, are either nomologically impossible or dismissible as exceptions to non-strict psychological laws.

The leading contemporary version of the Representational Theory of Mind, the Computational Theory of Mind (CTM), claims that the brain is a kind of computer and that mental processes are computations. According to CTM, cognitive states are constituted by computational relations to mental representations of various kinds, and cognitive processes are sequences of such states.

CTM develops RTM by attempting to explain all psychological states and processes in terms of mental representation. In the course of constructing detailed empirical theories of human and animal cognition and developing models of cognitive processes implementable in artificial information processing systems, cognitive scientists have proposed a variety of types of mental representations. While some of these may be suited to be mental relata of commonsense psychological states, some — so-called "subpersonal" or "sub-doxastic" representations — are not. Though many philosophers believe that CTM can provide the best scientific explanations of cognition and behavior, there is disagreement over whether such explanations will vindicate the commonsense psychological explanations of prescientific RTM.

According to Stich's (1983) Syntactic Theory of Mind, for example, computational theories of psychological states should concern themselves only with the formal properties of the objects those states are relations to. Commitment to the explanatory relevance of content , however, is for most cognitive scientists fundamental (Fodor 1981a, Pylyshyn 1984, Von Eckardt 1993). That mental processes are computations, that computations are rule-governed sequences of semantically evaluable objects , and that the rules apply to the symbols in virtue of their content, are central tenets of mainstream cognitive science.

Explanations in cognitive science appeal to a many different kinds of mental representation, including, for example, the "mental models" of Johnson-Laird 1983, the "retinal arrays," "primal sketches" and "2½ -D sketches" of Marr 1982, the "frames" of Minsky 1974, the "sub-symbolic" structures of Smolensky 1989, the "quasi-pictures"of Kosslyn 1980, and the "interpreted symbol-filled arrays" of Tye 1991 — in addition to representations that may be appropriate to the explanation of commonsense psychological states. Computational explanations have been offered of, among other mental phenomena, belief (Fodor 1975, Field 1978), visual perception (Marr 1982, Osherson, et al. 1990), rationality (Newell and Simon 1972, Fodor 1975, Johnson-Laird and Wason 1977), language learning and use (Chomsky 1965, Pinker 1989), and musical comprehension (Lerdahl and Jackendoff 1983).

A fundamental disagreement among proponents of CTM concerns the realization of personal-level representations (e.g., thoughts) and processes (e.g., inferences) in the brain. The central debate here is between proponents of Classical Architectures and proponents of Connectionist Architectures .

The classicists (e.g., Turing 1950, Fodor 1975, Fodor and Pylyshyn 1988, Marr 1982, Newell and Simon 1976) hold that mental representations are symbolic structures, which typically have semantically evaluable constituents, and that mental processes are rule-governed manipulations of them that are sensitive to their constituent structure. The connectionists (e.g., McCulloch & Pitts 1943, Rumelhart 1989, Rumelhart and McClelland 1986, Smolensky 1988) hold that mental representations are realized by patterns of activation in a network of simple processors ("nodes") and that mental processes consist of the spreading activation of such patterns. The nodes themselves are, typically, not taken to be semantically evaluable; nor do the patterns have semantically evaluable constituents. (Though there are versions of Connectionism — "localist" versions — on which individual nodes are taken to have semantic properties (e.g., Ballard 1986, Ballard & Hayes 1984).) It is arguable, however, that localist theories are neither definitive nor representative of the connectionist program (Smolensky 1988, 1991, Chalmers 1993).)

Classicists are motivated (in part) by properties thought seems to share with language. Fodor's Language of Thought Hypothesis (LOTH) (Fodor 1975, 1987), according to which the system of mental symbols constituting the neural basis of thought is structured like a language, provides a well-worked-out version of the classical approach as applied to commonsense psychology. (Cf. also Marr 1982 for an application of classical approach in scientific psychology.) According to the LOTH, the potential infinity of complex representational mental states is generated from a finite stock of primitive representational states, in accordance with recursive formation rules. This combinatorial structure accounts for the properties of productivity and systematicity of the system of mental representations. As in the case of symbolic languages, including natural languages (though Fodor does not suppose either that the LOTH explains only linguistic capacities or that only verbal creatures have this sort of cognitive architecture), these properties of thought are explained by appeal to the content of the representational units and their combinability into contentful complexes. That is, the semantics of both language and thought is compositional : the content of a complex representation is determined by the contents of its constituents and their structural configuration.

Connectionists are motivated mainly by a consideration of the architecture of the brain, which apparently consists of layered networks of interconnected neurons. They argue that this sort of architecture is unsuited to carrying out classical serial computations. For one thing, processing in the brain is typically massively parallel. In addition, the elements whose manipulation drives computation in connectionist networks (principally, the connections between nodes) are neither semantically compositional nor semantically evaluable, as they are on the classical approach. This contrast with classical computationalism is often characterized by saying that representation is, with respect to computation, distributed as opposed to local : representation is local if it is computationally basic; and distributed if it is not. (Another way of putting this is to say that for classicists mental representations are computationally atomic , whereas for connectionists they are not.)

Moreover, connectionists argue that information processing as it occurs in connectionist networks more closely resembles some features of actual human cognitive functioning. For example, whereas on the classical view learning involves something like hypothesis formation and testing (Fodor 1981c), on the connectionist model it is a matter of evolving distribution of "weight" (strength) on the connections between nodes, and typically does not involve the formulation of hypotheses regarding the identity conditions for the objects of knowledge. The connectionist network is "trained up" by repeated exposure to the objects it is to learn to distinguish; and, though networks typically require many more exposures to the objects than do humans, this seems to model at least one feature of this type of human learning quite well. (Cf. the sonar example in Churchland 1989.)

Further, degradation in the performance of such networks in response to damage is gradual, not sudden as in the case of a classical information processor, and hence more accurately models the loss of human cognitive function as it typically occurs in response to brain damage. It is also sometimes claimed that connectionist systems show the kind of flexibility in response to novel situations typical of human cognition — situations in which classical systems are relatively "brittle" or "fragile."

Some philosophers have maintained that connectionism entails that there are no propositional attitudes. Ramsey, Stich and Garon (1990) have argued that if connectionist models of cognition are basically correct, then there are no discrete representational states as conceived in ordinary commonsense psychology and classical cognitive science. Others, however (e.g., Smolensky 1989), hold that certain types of higher-level patterns of activity in a neural network may be roughly identified with the representational states of commonsense psychology. Still others (e.g., Fodor & Pylyshyn 1988, Heil 1991, Horgan and Tienson 1996) argue that language-of-thought style representation is both necessary in general and realizable within connectionist architectures. (MacDonald & MacDonald 1995 collects the central contemporary papers in the classicist/connectionist debate, and provides useful introductory material as well. See also Von Eckardt 2004.)

Whereas Stich (1983) accepts that mental processes are computational, but denies that computations are sequences of mental representations, others accept the notion of mental representation, but deny that CTM provides the correct account of mental states and processes.

Van Gelder (1995) denies that psychological processes are computational. He argues that cognitive systems are dynamic , and that cognitive states are not relations to mental symbols, but quantifiable states of a complex system consisting of (in the case of human beings) a nervous system, a body and the environment in which they are embedded. Cognitive processes are not rule-governed sequences of discrete symbolic states, but continuous, evolving total states of dynamic systems determined by continuous, simultaneous and mutually determining states of the systems' components. Representation in a dynamic system is essentially information-theoretic, though the bearers of information are not symbols, but state variables or parameters. (See also Port and Van Gelder 1995; Clark 1997a, 1997b.)

Horst (1996), on the other hand, argues that though computational models may be useful in scientific psychology, they are of no help in achieving a philosophical understanding of the intentionality of commonsense mental states. CTM attempts to reduce the intentionality of such states to the intentionality of the mental symbols they are relations to. But, Horst claims, the relevant notion of symbolic content is essentially bound up with the notions of convention and intention. So CTM involves itself in a vicious circularity: the very properties that are supposed to be reduced are (tacitly) appealed to in the reduction.

To say that a mental object has semantic properties is, paradigmatically, to say that it may be about , or be true or false of, an object or objects, or that it may be true or false simpliciter . Suppose I think that ocelots take snuff. I am thinking about ocelots, and if what I think of them (that they take snuff) is true of them, then my thought is true. According to RTM such states are to be explained as relations between agents and mental representations. To think that ocelots take snuff is to token in some way a mental representation whose content is that ocelots take snuff. On this view, the semantic properties of mental states are the semantic properties of the representations they are relations to.

Linguistic acts seem to share such properties with mental states. Suppose I say that ocelots take snuff. I am talking about ocelots, and if what I say of them (that they take snuff) is true of them, then my utterance is true. Now, to say that ocelots take snuff is (in part) to utter a sentence that means that ocelots take snuff. Many philosophers have thought that the semantic properties of linguistic expressions are inherited from the intentional mental states they are conventionally used to express (Grice 1957, Fodor 1978, Schiffer1972/1988, Searle 1983). On this view, the semantic properties of linguistic expressions are the semantic properties of the representations that are the mental relata of the states they are conventionally used to express.

(Others, however, e.g., Davidson (1975, 1982) have suggested that the kind of thought human beings are capable of is not possible without language, so that the dependency might be reversed, or somehow mutual (see also Sellars 1956). (But see Martin 1987 for a defense of the claim that thought is possible without language. See also Chisholm and Sellars 1958.) Schiffer (1987) subsequently despaired of the success of what he calls "Intention Based Semantics.")

It is also widely held that in addition to having such properties as reference, truth-conditions and truth — so-called extensional properties — expressions of natural languages also have intensional properties, in virtue of expressing properties or propositions — i.e., in virtue of having meanings or senses , where two expressions may have the same reference, truth-conditions or truth value, yet express different properties or propositions (Frege 1892/1997). If the semantic properties of natural-language expressions are inherited from the thoughts and concepts they express (or vice versa, or both), then an analogous distinction may be appropriate for mental representations.

  • Almog, J., Perry, J. and Wettstein, H., eds. (1989), Themes from Kaplan , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Aristotle, (1984), De Anima , in The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Baker, L. R. (1995), Explaining Attitudes: A Practical Approach to the Mind , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Ballard, D.H. (1986), "Cortical Connections and Parallel Processing: Structure and Function," The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9: 67-120.
  • Ballard, D.H and Hayes, P.J. (1984), "Parallel Logical Inference," Proceedings of the Sixth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society , Rochester, NY.
  • Beaney, M. ed., (1997), The Frege Reader , Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
  • Berkeley, G. (1975), Principles of Human Knowledge , in M.R. Ayers, ed., Berkeley: Philosophical Writings , London: Dent.
  • Block, N. ed., (1981), Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, Vol. 2 , Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • Block, N. ed., (1982), Imagery , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Block, N. (1983), "Mental Pictures and Cognitive Science," Philosophical Review 93: 499-542.
  • Block, N. (1986), "Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology," in P.A. French, T.E. Uehling and H.K. Wettstein, eds., Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Vol. X , Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press: 615-678.
  • Block, N. (1996), "Mental Paint and Mental Latex," in E. Villanueva, ed., Philosophical Issues, 7: Perception : 19-49.
  • Block, N. (2003), "Mental Paint," in M. Hahn and B. Ramberg, eds., Reflections and Replies: Essays on the Philosophy of Tyler Burge , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Boghossian, P. A. (1995), "Content," in J. Kim and E. Sosa, eds., A Companion to Metaphysics , Oxford: Blackwell Publishers Ltd.: 94-96.
  • Brandom, R. (2002), "Non-inferential Knowledge, Perceptual Experience, and Secondary Qualities: Placing McDowell's Empiricism," in N.H. Smith, ed., Reading McDowell: On Mind and World , London: Routledge.
  • Burge, T. (1979), "Individualism and the Mental," in P.A. French, T.E. Uehling and H.K.Wettstein, eds., Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Vol. IV , Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press: 73-121.
  • Burge, T. (1986a), "Individualism and Psychology," Philosophical Review 95: 3-45.
  • Burge, T. (1986b), "Intellectual Norms and Foundations of Mind," The Journal of Philosophy 83: 697-720.
  • Chalmers, D. (1993), "Connectionism and Compositionality: Why Fodor and Pylyshyn Were Wrong," Philosophical Psychology 6: 305-319.
  • Chalmers, D. (1996), The Conscious Mind , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Chalmers, D. (2003), "The Content and Epistemology of Phenomenal Belief," in Q. Smith & A. Jokic, eds., Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives , Oxford: Oxford University Press: 220-272.
  • Chalmers, D. (forthcoming), "The Representational Character of Experience," in B. Leiter, ed., The Future for Philosophy , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Chisholm, R. and Sellars, W. (1958), "The Chisholm-Sellars Correspondence on Intentionality," in H. Feigl, M. Scriven and G. Maxwell, eds., Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. II , Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press: 529-539.
  • Chomsky, N. (1965), Aspects of the Theory of Syntax , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Churchland, P.M. (1981), "Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes," Journal of Philosophy 78: 67-90.
  • Churchland, P.M. (1989), "On the Nature of Theories: A Neurocomputational Perspective," in W. Savage, ed., Scientific Theories: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science , Vol. 14, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press: 59-101.
  • Clark, A. (1997a), "The Dynamical Challenge," Cognitive Science 21: 461-481.
  • Clark, A. (1997b), Being There: Putting Brain, Body and World Together Again , Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  • Collins, A. (1987), The Nature of Mental Things , Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press.
  • Crane, T. (1995), The Mechanical Mind , London: Penguin Books Ltd.
  • Davidson, D. (1973), "Radical Interpretation," Dialectica 27: 313-328.
  • Davidson, D. (1974), "Belief and the Basis of Meaning," Synthese 27: 309-323.
  • Davidson, D. (1975), "Thought and Talk," in S. Guttenplan, ed., Mind and Language , Oxford: Clarendon Press: 7-23.
  • Davidson, D. (1982), "Rational Animals," Dialectica 4: 317-327.
  • Dennett, D. (1969), Content and Consciousness , London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Dennett, D. (1981), "The Nature of Images and the Introspective Trap," pages 132-141 of Dennett 1969, reprinted in Block 1981: 128-134.
  • Dennett, D. (1987), The Intentional Stance , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Dennett, D. (1987a), "True Believers: The Intentional Strategy and Why it Works," in Dennett 1987: 13-35.
  • Dennett, D. (1987b), "Reflections: Real Patterns, Deeper Facts, and Empty Questions," in Dennett 1987: 37-42.
  • Dennett, D. (1988), "Quining Qualia," in A.J. Marcel and E. Bisiach, eds., Consciousness in Contemporary Science , Oxford: Clarendon Press: 42-77.
  • Dennett, D. (1991), "Real Patterns," The Journal of Philosophy 87: 27-51.
  • Devitt, M. (1996), Coming to Our Senses: A Naturalistic Program for Semantic Localism , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Dretske, F. (1969), Seeing and Knowing , Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
  • Dretske, F. (1981), Knowledge and the Flow of Information , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Dretske, F. (1988), Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Dretske, F. (1995), Naturalizing the Mind , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Dretske, F. (1998), "Minds, Machines, and Money: What Really Explains Behavior," in J. Bransen and S. Cuypers, eds., Human Action, Deliberation and Causation, Philosophical Studies Series 77 , Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Reprinted in Dretske 2000.
  • Dretske, F. (2000), Perception, Knowledge and Belief , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Evans, G. (1982), The Varieties of Reference , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Field, H. (1978), "Mental representation," Erkenntnis 13: 9-61.
  • Flanagan, O. (1992), Consciousness Reconsidered , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Fodor, J.A. (1975), The Language of Thought , Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • Fodor, J.A. (1978), "Propositional Attitudes," The Monist 61: 501-523.
  • Fodor, J.A. (1981), Representations , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Fodor, J.A. (1981a), "Introduction," in Fodor 1981: 1-31.
  • Fodor, J.A. (1981b), "Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology," in Fodor 1981: 225-253.
  • Fodor, J.A. (1981c), "The Present Status of the Innateness Controversy," in Fodor 1981: 257-316.
  • Fodor, J.A. (1982), "Cognitive Science and the Twin-Earth Problem," Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 23: 98-118.
  • Fodor, J.A. (1987), Psychosemantics , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Fodor, J.A. (1990a), A Theory of Content and Other Essays , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Fodor, J.A. (1990b), "Psychosemantics or: Where Do Truth Conditions Come From?" in W.G. Lycan, ed., Mind and Cognition: A Reader , Oxford: Blackwell Publishers: 312-337.
  • Fodor, J.A. (1994), The Elm and the Expert , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Fodor, J.A. (1998), Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Fodor, J.A. and Pylyshyn, Z. (1981), "How Direct is Visual Perception?: Some Reflections on Gibson's ‘Ecological Approach’," Cognition 9: 207-246.
  • Fodor, J.A. and Pylyshyn, Z. (1988), "Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture: A Critical Analysis," Cognition 28: 3-71.
  • Frege, G. (1884), The Foundations of Arithmetic , trans. J.L. Austin, New York: Philosophical Library (1954).
  • Frege, G. (1892), "On Sinn and Bedeutung ", in Beany 1997: 151-171.
  • Frege, G. (1918), "Thought", in Beany 1997: 325-345.
  • Geach, P. (1957), Mental Acts: Their Content and Their Objects , London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Gibson, J.J. (1966), The senses considered as perceptual systems , Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
  • Gibson, J.J. (1979), The ecological approach to visual perception , Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
  • Goldman, A. (1993), "The Psychology of Folk Psychology," Behavioral and Brian Sciences 16: 15-28.
  • Goodman, N. (1976), Languages of Art (2nd ed.), Indianapolis: Hackett.
  • Grice, H.P. (1957), "Meaning," Philosophical Review , 66: 377-388; reprinted in Studies in the Way of Words , Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press (1989): 213-223.
  • Gunther, Y.H. (ed.) (2003), Essays on Nonconceptual Content , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Harman, G. (1973), Thought , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Harman, G. 1987, "(Non-Solipsistic) Conceptual Role Semantics," in E. Lepore, ed., New Directions in Semantics , London: Academic Press: 55-81.
  • Harman, G. 1990, "The Intrinsic Quality of Experience," in J. Tomberlin, ed., Philosophical Perspectives 4: Action Theory and Philosophy of Mind , Atascadero: Ridgeview Publishing Company: 31-52.
  • Harnish, R. (2002), Minds, Brains, Computers , Malden, Mass.: Blackwell Publishers Inc.
  • Haugeland, J. (1981), "Analog and analog," Philosophical Topics 12: 213-226.
  • Heil, J. (1991), "Being Indiscrete," in J. Greenwood, ed., The Future of Folk Psychology , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 120-134.
  • Horgan, T. and Tienson, J. (1996), Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology , Cambridge, Mass: The MIT Press.
  • Horgan, T. and Tiensen, J. (2003), "The Intentionality of Phenomenology and the Phenomenology of Intentionality," in D.J. Chalmers, ed., Philosophy of Mind , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Horst, S. (1996), Symbols, Computation, and Intentionality , Berkeley: University of California Press.
  • Hume, D. (1739), A Treatise of Human Nature , ed. L.A. Selby-Bigg, rev. P.H. Nidditch, Oxford: Oxford University Press (1978).
  • Jackendoff, R. (1987), Computation and Cognition , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Jackson, F. (1982), "Epiphenomenal Qualia," Philosophical Quarterly 32: 127-136.
  • Jackson, F. (1986), "What Mary Didn't Know," Journal of Philosophy 83: 291-295.
  • Johnson-Laird, P.N. and Wason, P.C. (1977), Thinking: Readings in Cognitive Science , Cambridge University Press.
  • Johnson-Laird, P.N. (1983), Mental Models , Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • Kaplan, D. (1989), "Demonstratives," in Almog, Perry and Wettstein 1989: 481-614.
  • Kosslyn, S.M. (1980), Image and Mind , Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • Kosslyn, S.M. (1982), "The Medium and the Message in Mental Imagery," in Block 1982: 207-246.
  • Kosslyn, S. (1983), Ghosts in the Mind's Machine , New York: W.W. Norton & Co.
  • Kosslyn, S.M. and Pomerantz, J.R. (1977), "Imagery, Propositions, and the Form of Internal Representations," Cognitive Psychology 9: 52-76.
  • Leeds, S. (1993), "Qualia, Awareness, Sellars," Noûs XXVII: 303-329.
  • Lerdahl, F. and Jackendoff, R. (1983), A Generative Theory of Tonal Music , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Levine, J. (1993), "On Leaving Out What It's Like," in M. Davies and G. Humphreys, eds., Consciousness , Oxford: Blackwell Publishers: 121-136.
  • Levine, J. (1995), "On What It Is Like to Grasp a Concept," in E. Villanueva, ed., Philosophical Issues 6: Content , Atascadero: Ridgeview Publishing Company: 38-43.
  • Levine, J. (2001), Purple Haze , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Lewis, D. (1971), "Analog and Digital," Noûs 5: 321-328.
  • Lewis, D. (1974), "Radical Interpretation," Synthese 27: 331-344.
  • Loar, B. (1981), Mind and Meaning , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Loar, B. (1996), "Phenomenal States" (Revised Version), in N. Block, O. Flanagan and G. Güzeldere, eds., The Nature of Consciousness , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press: 597-616.
  • Loar, B. (2003a), "Transparent Experience and the Availability of Qualia," in Q. Smith and A. Jokic, eds., Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives , Oxford: Clarendon Press: 77-96.
  • Loar, B. (2003b), "Phenomenal Intentionality as the Basis of Mental Content," in M. Hahn and B. Ramberg, eds., Reflections and Replies: Essays on the Philosophy of Tyler Burge , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Locke, J. (1689), An Essay Concerning Human Understanding , ed. P.H. Nidditch, Oxford: Oxford University Press (1975).
  • Lycan, W.G. (1987), Consciousness , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Lycan, W.G. (1986), Consciousness and Experience , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • MacDonald, C. and MacDonald, G. (1995), Connectionism: Debates on Psychological Explanation , Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
  • Marr, D. (1982), Vision , New York: W.H. Freeman and Company.
  • Martin, C.B. (1987), "Proto-Language," Australasian Journal of Philosophy 65: 277-289.
  • McCulloch, W.S. and Pitts, W., (1943), "A Logical Calculus of the Ideas Immanent in Nervous Activity," Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics 5: 115-33.
  • McDowell, J. (1994), Mind and World , Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • McGinn, C. (1977), "Charity, Interpretation, and Belief," Journal of Philosophy 74:
  • McGinn, C. (1982), "The Structure of Content," in A. Woodfield, ed., Thought and Content , Oxford: Oxford University Press: 207-258.
  • McGinn, C. (1989), Mental Content , Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
  • McGinn, C. (1991), The Problem of Consciousness , Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
  • McGinn, C. (1991a), "Content and Consciousness," in McGinn 1991: 23-43.
  • McGinn, C. (1991b), "Can We Solve the Mind-Body Problem?" in McGinn 1991: 1-22.
  • Millikan, R. (1984), Language, Thought and other Biological Categories , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Minsky, M. (1974), "A Framework for Representing Knowledge," MIT-AI Laboratory Memo 306 June. (A shorter version appears in J. Haugeland, ed., Mind Design II , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press (1997).)
  • Nagel, T. (1974), "What Is It Like to Be a Bat?" Philosophical Review 83: 435-450.
  • Newell, A. and Simon, H.A. (1972), Human Problem Solving , New York: Prentice-Hall.
  • Newell, A. and Simon, H.A. (1976), "Computer Science as Empirical Inquiry: Symbols and Search," Communications of the Association for Computing Machinery 19: 113-126.
  • Osherson, D.N., Kosslyn, S.M. and Hollerbach, J.M. (1990), Visual Cognition and Action: An Invitation to Cognitive Science, Vol. 2 , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Papineau, D. (1987), Reality and Representation , Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
  • Peacocke, C. (1983), Sense and Content , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Peacocke, C. (1989), "Perceptual Content," in Almog, Perry and Wettstein 1989: 297-329.
  • Peacocke, C. (1992), "Scenarios, Concepts and Perception," in T. Crane, ed., The Contents of Experience , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 105-35.
  • Peacocke, C. (2001), "Does Perception Have a Nonconceptual Content?" Journal of Philosophy 99: 239-264.
  • Pinker, S. (1989), Learnability and Cognition , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Pitt, D. (2004), "The Phenomenology of Cognition, Or, What Is it Like to Think That P?" Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69.
  • Port, R., and Van Gelder, T. (1995), Mind as Motion: Explorations in the Dynamics of Cognition , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Putnam, H. (1975), "The Meaning of ‘Meaning’," in Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2 , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 215-71.
  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1979), "The Rate of ‘Mental Rotation’ of Images: A Test of a Holistic Analogue Hypothesis," Memory and Cognition , 7: 19-28.
  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1981a), "Imagery and Artificial Intelligence," in Block 1981: 170-194.
  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1981b), "The Imagery Debate: Analog Media versus Tacit Knowledge," Psychological Review 88: 16-45.
  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1984), Computation and Cognition , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Pylyshyn, Z. (2003), Seeing and Visualizing: It's Not What You Think , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Raffman, D. (1995), "The Persistence of Phenomenology," in T. Metzinger, ed., Conscious Experience , Paderborn: Schönigh/Imprint Academic: 293-308.
  • Ramsey, W., Stich, S. and Garon, J. (1990), "Connectionism, Eliminativism and the Future of Folk Psychology," Philosophical Perspectives 4: 499-533.
  • Reid, T. (1764), An Inquiry into the Human Mind , D.R. Brooks, ed., Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press (1997).
  • Rey, G. (1981), "Introduction: What Are Mental Images?" in Block 1981: 117-127.
  • Rey, G. (1991), "Sensations in a Language of Thought," in E. Villaneuva, ed., Philosophical Issues 1: Consciousness , Atascadero: Ridgeview Publishing Company: 73-112.
  • Rumelhart, D.E. (1989), "The Architecture of the Mind: A Connectionist Approach," in M.I. Posner, ed., Foundations of Cognitive Science , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press: 133-159.
  • Rumelhart, D.E. and McCelland, J.L. (1986). Parallel Distributed Processing, Vol. I , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Schiffer, S. (1987), Remnants of Meaning , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Schiffer, S. (1972), "Introduction to the Paperback Edition," in Meaning , Oxford: Clarendon Press (1972/1988): xi-xxix.
  • Searle, J.R. (1980), "Minds, Brains, and Programs," Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3: 417-424.
  • Searle, J.R. (1983), Intentionality , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Searle, J.R. (1984) Minds, Brains, and Science , Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • Searle, J.R. (1992), The Rediscovery of the Mind , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Sellars, W. (1956), "Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind," in K. Gunderson, ed., Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. I , Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press: 253-329.
  • Shepard, R.N. and Cooper, L. (1982), Mental Images and their Transformations , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Shoemaker, S. (1990), "Qualities and Qualia: What's in the Mind?" Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50: 109-31.
  • Smolensky, P. (1988), "On the Proper Treatment of Connectionism," Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 11: 1-74.
  • Siewert, C. (1998), The Significance of Consciousness , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Smolensky, P. (1989), "Connectionist Modeling: Neural Computation/Mental Connections," in L. Nadel, L.A. Cooper, P. Culicover and R.M. Harnish, eds., Neural Connections, Mental Computation Cambridge, Mass.:The MIT Press: 49-67.
  • Smolensky, P. (1991), "Connectionism and the Language of Thought," in B. Loewer and G. Rey, eds., Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics , Oxford: Basil Blackwell Ltd.: 201-227.
  • Sterelny, K. (1989), "Fodor's Nativism," Philosophical Studies 55: 119-141.
  • Stich, S. (1983), From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Stich, S. (1996), Deconstructing the Mind , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Strawson, G. (1994), Mental Reality , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Thau, M. (2002), Consciousness and Cognition , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Turing, A. (1950), "Computing Machinery and Intelligence," Mind 59: 433-60.
  • Tye, M. (1991), The Imagery Debate , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Tye, M. (1995), Ten Problems of Consciousness , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Tye, M. (2000), Consciousness, Color, and Content , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Van Gelder, T. (1995), "What Might Cognition Be, if not Computation?", Journal of Philosophy XCI: 345-381.
  • Von Eckardt, B. (1993), What Is Cognitive Science? , Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
  • Von Eckardt, B. (forthcoming, June 2004), "Connectionism and the Propositional Attitudes," in C.E. Erneling and D.M. Johnson, eds., The Mind as a Scientific Object: Between Brain and Culture , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953), Philosophical Investigations , trans. G.E.M. Anscombe, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
  • A Field Guide to the Philosophy of Mind , General editors, Marcho Nani and Massimo Marraffa.
  • Cogprints , Cognitive Sciences Eprint Archive, University of Southampton.
  • Annotated Bibliography of Contemporary Philosophy of Mind , maintained by David Chalmers, University of Arizona.
  • Dictionary of Philosophy of Mind , Editor, Chris Eliasmith, Washington University in St. Louis.
  • DON'T PANIC: Tye's Intentionalist Theory of Consciousness , by Alex Byrne, from A Field Guide to the Philosophy of Mind .

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Brad Armour-Garb, Mark Balaguer, Dave Chalmers, Jim Garson, John Heil, Jeff Poland, Bill Robinson, Galen Strawson, Adam Vinueza and (especially) Barbara Von Eckardt for comments on earlier versions of this entry.

A | B | C | D | E | F | G | H | I | J | K | L | M | N | O | P | Q | R | S | T | U | V | W | X | Y | Z

1. representation

  • Rhymes with Mental-representation

2. representation

3. representation, 4. representation, 5. representation, 6. representation, 7. representation.

noun. ['ˌrɛprəzɛnˈteɪʃən'] a creation that is a visual or tangible rendering of someone or something.

  • cutaway drawing
  • illustration
  • Station of the Cross
  • objectification
  • cutaway model
  • adumbration
  • cosmography
  • presentation
  • depressurize
  • desynchronize
  • desynchronise

Rhymes with Mental Representation

  • deinstitutionalization
  • institutionalization
  • self-congratulation
  • antidiscrimination
  • telecommunication
  • nondiscrimination
  • misrepresentation
  • mischaracterization
  • internationalization
  • industrialization
  • decriminalization
  • transillumination
  • self-determination
  • renationalization
  • recapitalization
  • prestidigitation
  • misinterpretation
  • misidentification
  • miscommunication
  • experimentation
  • excommunication
  • disqualification
  • discontinuation
  • denationalization
  • decentralization
  • transplantation
  • singularization
  • self-perpetuation
  • securitization
  • reinterpretation

noun. ['ˌrɛprəzɛnˈteɪʃən'] a presentation to the mind in the form of an idea or image.

  • intersection
  • mental representation
  • convergence
  • mental image
  • cognitive content
  • psychosexuality
  • internal representation
  • concrete representation
  • phantasmagoria
  • mental object
  • perceptual experience
  • instantiation
  • interpretation
  • abstractionism

noun. ['ˌrɛprəzɛnˈteɪʃən'] the act of representing; standing in for someone or some group and speaking with authority in their behalf.

  • cooperation
  • depressurise

noun. ['ˌrɛprəzɛnˈteɪʃən'] an activity that stands as an equivalent of something or results in an equivalent.

  • dramatization
  • schematization
  • dramatisation
  • pictorial representation
  • diagramming
  • typification
  • deglycerolize

noun. ['ˌrɛprəzɛnˈteɪʃən'] a statement of facts and reasons made in appealing or protesting.

noun. ['ˌrɛprəzɛnˈteɪʃən'] a performance of a play.

  • theatrical performance
  • performance
  • public presentation
  • invulnerability
  • natural object

noun. ['ˌrɛprəzɛnˈteɪʃən'] the state of serving as an official and authorized delegate or agent.

  • legal representation
  • free agency
  • colorlessness

adjective. ['ˈmɛntəl'] involving the mind or an intellectual process.

  • intellectual
  • psychological
  • psychogenic
  • dishonorable
  • mental (Middle French (ca. 1400-1600))
  • mentalis (Latin)

adjective. ['ˈmɛntəl'] affected by a disorder of the mind.

adjective. ['ˈmɛntəl'] of or relating to the chin or median part of the lower jaw.

  • unrighteous

synonym term image

download a flashcard

Uncovering the interplay between drawings, mental representations, and arithmetic problem-solving strategies in children and adults

  • Published: 12 February 2024

Cite this article

another name for a mental representation is cognitive sketch

  • Hippolyte Gros   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-4151-0715 1 ,
  • Jean-Pierre Thibaut 2 &
  • Emmanuel Sander 3  

335 Accesses

59 Altmetric

Explore all metrics

There is an ongoing debate in the scientific community regarding the nature and role of the mental representations involved in solving arithmetic word problems. In this study, we took a closer look at the interplay between mental representations, drawing production, and strategy choice. We used dual-strategy isomorphic word problems sharing the same mathematical structure, but differing in the entities they mentioned in their problem statement. Due to the non-mathematical knowledge attached to these entities, some problems were believed to lead to a specific (cardinal) encoding compatible with one solving strategy, whereas other problems were thought to foster a different (ordinal) encoding compatible with the other solving strategy. We asked 59 children and 52 adults to solve 12 of those arithmetic word problems and to make a diagram of each problem. We hypothesized that the diagrams of both groups would display prototypical features indicating either a cardinal representation or an ordinal representation, depending on the entities mentioned in the problem statement. Joint analysis of the drawing task and the problem-solving task showed that the cardinal and ordinal features of the diagrams are linked with the hypothesized semantic properties of the problems and, crucially, with the choice of one solving strategy over another. We showed that regardless of their experience, participants’ strategy use depends on their problem representation, which is influenced by the non-mathematical information in the problem statement, as revealed in their diagrams. We discuss the relevance of drawing tasks for investigating mental representations and fostering mathematical development in school.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price includes VAT (Russian Federation)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Rent this article via DeepDyve

Institutional subscriptions

another name for a mental representation is cognitive sketch

Similar content being viewed by others

another name for a mental representation is cognitive sketch

Decision Making: a Theoretical Review

Extending cognitive load theory to incorporate working memory resource depletion: evidence from the spacing effect, word problems in mathematics education: a survey, data availability.

All data and materials for this study are available online at https://osf.io/nhp4e/?view_only=6a5e4fd4dedb4811a994030b988033a8 .

Agrell, B., & Dehlin, O. (1998). The clock-drawing test. Age and ageing, 27 (3), 399–404. https://doi.org/10.1093/ageing/afs149

Article   Google Scholar  

Anderson, S. F., & Kelley, K. (2018), BUCSS: Bias and Uncertainty Corrected Sample Size [computer software and manual]. R package version 1.2.1, https://CRAN.R-project.org/package=BUCSS

Anderson, S. F., Kelley, K., & Maxwell, S. E. (2017). Sample-size planning for more accurate statistical power: A method adjusting sample effect sizes for publication bias and uncertainty. Psychological Science, 28 (11), 1547–1562

Article   PubMed   Google Scholar  

Baccaglini-Frank, A., Carotenuto, G., & Sinclair, N. (2020). Eliciting preschoolers’ number abilities using open, multi-touch environments. ZDM, 52 , 779–791.

Bagnoud, J., Burra, N., Castel, C., Oakhill, J., & Thevenot, C. (2018). Arithmetic word problems describing discrete quantities: EEG evidence for the construction of a situation model. Acta Psychologica, 190 , 116–121.

Bainbridge, W. A. (2022). A tutorial on capturing mental representations through drawing and crowd-sourced scoring. Behavior Research Methods, 54 (2), 663–675.

Bainbridge, W. A., Hall, E. H., & Baker, C. I. (2019). Drawings of real-world scenes during free recall reveal detailed object and spatial information in memory. Nature communications, 10 (1), 5.

Article   CAS   PubMed   PubMed Central   Google Scholar  

Bakar, K. A., Way, J., & Bobis, J. (2016). Young children’s drawings in problem solving . Mathematics Education Research Group of Australasia.

Google Scholar  

Barrios, F. M. G., & Martínez, E. C. (2014). Diagrams produced by secondary students in multiplicative comparison word problems. Journal of Mathematics and System Science, 4 (2), 83.

Bassok, M. (2001). Semantic alignments in mathematical word problems. In D. Gentner, K. J. Holyoak, & B. N. Kokinov (Eds.), The analogical mind: Perspectives from cognitive science (pp. 401–433). MIT Press.

Chapter   Google Scholar  

Berkum, J. J. V., Hagoort, P., & Brown, C. M. (1999). Semantic integration in sentences and discourse: Evidence from the N400. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 11 (6), 657–671.

Bermejo, V. (1996). Cardinality development and counting. Developmental Psychology, 32 (2), 263–268.

Burgess, A. W., & Hartman, C. R. (1993). Children’s drawings. Child Abuse & Neglect, 17 (1), 161–168.

Article   CAS   Google Scholar  

Carruthers, E., & Worthington, M. (2003). Children’s mathematics: making marks, making meaning . Sage.

Chamberlain, R., & Wagemans, J. (2016). The genesis of errors in drawing. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 65 , 195–207.

Cheung, C. N., & Lourenco, S. F. (2019). Does 1+ 1= 2nd? The relations between children’s understanding of ordinal position and their arithmetic performance. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 187 , 104651.

Colomé, À., & Noël, M. P. (2012). One first? Acquisition of the cardinal and ordinal uses of numbers in preschoolers. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 113 (2), 233–247.

Coquin-Viennot, D., & Moreau, S. (2003). Highlighting the role of episodic model in the solving of arithmetical problems. European Journal of Psychology and Education, 18 , 267–279.

Cox, R. (1999). Representation construction, externalised cognition and individual differences. Learning and Instruction, 9 (4), 343–363.

Crespo, S. M., & Kyriakides, A. O. (2007). Research, Reflection, Practice: To Draw or Not to Draw: Exploring Children’s Drawings for Solving Mathematics Problems. Teaching Children Mathematics, 14 (2), 118–125.

Csíkos, C., Szitányi, J., & Kelemen, R. (2012). The effects of using drawings in developing young children’s mathematical word problem solving: A design experiment with third-grade Hungarian students. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 81 (1), 47–65.

Cummins, D. D. (1991). Children’s interpretations of arithmetic word problems. Cognition and Instruction, 8 (3), 261–289.

Dantzig, T. (1945). Number the language of science. A critical survey written for the cultured non-mathematician . The Macmillan Company.

Daroczy, G., Wolska, M., Meurers, W. D., & Nuerk, H. C. (2015). Word problems: A review of linguistic and numerical factors contributing to their difficulty. Frontiers in Psychology, 6 , 348.

Article   PubMed   PubMed Central   Google Scholar  

Dauben, J. W. (1990). Georg Cantor: His mathematics and philosophy of the infinite . Princeton University Press.

De Bock, D., & Verschaffel, Janssens D. (1998). The predominance of linear model in secondary students’ solutions of word problems involving length and area of similar plane figures. Education Studies in Mathematics, 35 (1), 65–83.

De Bock, D., Verschaffel, L., Janssens, D., Van Dooren, W., & Claes, K. (2003). Do realistic contexts and graphical representations always have a beneficial impact on students’ performance? Negative evidence from a study on modelling non-linear geometry problems. Learning and Instruction, 13 (4), 441–463.

De Corte, E., Verschaffel, L., & De Win, L. (1985). Influence of rewording verbal problems on children’s problem representations and solution. Journal of Educational Psychology, 77 , 460–470.

Draschkow, D., Wolfe, J. M., & Vo, M. L. H. (2014). Seek and you shall remember: Scene semantics interact with visual search to build better memories. Journal of Vision, 14 (8), 10–10.

Edens, K., & Potter, E. (2007). The relationship of drawing and mathematical problem solving: Draw for math tasks. Studies in Art Education, 48 (3), 282–298.

Edens, K., & Potter, E. (2008). How students “unpack” the structure of a word problem: Graphic representations and problem solving. School Science and Mathematics, 108 (5), 184–196.

Ericsson, K. A., & Simon, H. A. (1980). Verbal reports as data. Psychological Review, 87 (3), 215.

Fan, J. E. (2015). Drawing to learn: How producing graphical representations enhances scientific thinking. Translational Issues in Psychological Science, 1 (2), 170.

Fan, J. E., Hawkins, R. D., Wu, M., & Goodman, N. D. (2020). Pragmatic inference and visual abstraction enable contextual flexibility during visual communication. Computational Brain & Behavior, 3 , 86–101.

Fischer, F. E., & Beckey, R. D. (1990). Beginning kindergarteners’ perception of number. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 70 (2), 419–425.

Article   CAS   PubMed   Google Scholar  

Fischer, J. P., Sander, E., Sensevy, G., Vilette, B., & Richard, J. F. (2019). Can young students understand the mathematical concept of equality? A whole-year arithmetic teaching experiment in second grade. European Journal of Psychology of Education, 34 (2), 439–456.

Fourtassi, M., Rode, G., & Pisella, L. (2017). Using eye movements to explore mental representations of space. Annals of Physical and Rehabilitation Medicine, 60 (3), 160–163.

Freeman, N. H., & Janikoun, R. (1972). Intellectual realism in children’s drawings of a familiar object with distinctive features. Child Development, 1116–1121. https://doi.org/10.2307/1127668

Frege, G. (1984). The Foundations of Arithmetic  (J. Austin, Trans.) Northwestern University Press.

Fuhrman, O., & Boroditsky, L. (2010). Cross-cultural differences in mental representations of time: Evidence from an implicit nonlinguistic task. Cognitive Science, 34 (8), 1430–1451.

Gainotti, G., & Trojano, L. (2018). Constructional apraxia. Handbook of Clinical Neurology, 151 , 331–348.

Gamo, S., Sander, E., & Richard, J.-F. (2010). Transfer of strategy use by semantic recoding in arithmetic problem solving. Learning and Instruction, 20 (5), 400–410.

Geary, D. C. (2018). Growth of symbolic number knowledge accelerates after children understand cardinality. Cognition, 177 , 69–78.

Geary, D. C., vanMarle, K., Chu, F. W., Rouder, J., Hoard, M. K., & Nugent, L. (2018). Early conceptual understanding of cardinality predicts superior school-entry number-system knowledge. Psychological science, 29 (2), 191–205.

Goffin, C., & Ansari, D. (2016). Beyond magnitude: Judging ordinality of symbolic number is unrelated to magnitude comparison and independently relates to individual differences in arithmetic. Cognition, 150 , 68–76.

Gros, H., & Gvozdic, K. (2022). Context, content effects and flexibility. In E. Clément (Eds.), Cognitive Flexibility: The Cornerstone of Learning  (pp. 203–232). https://doi.org/10.1002/9781119902737.ch8

Gros, H., Sander, E., & Thibaut, J. P. (2019). When masters of abstraction run into a concrete wall: Experts failing arithmetic word problems. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review , https://doi.org/10.3758/s13423-019-01628-3 online first.

Gros, H., Sander, E., & Thibaut, J. P. (2020a). Are content effects out of sight? An eye-tracking study of arithmetic problem solving. In S. Denison., M. Mack, Y. Xu, & B. C. Armstrong (Eds.), Proceedings of the 42nd Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society . Cognitive Science Society.

Gros, H., Thibaut, J. P., & Sander, E. (2020b). Semantic congruence in arithmetic: A new conceptual model for word problem solving. Educational Psychologist, 55 (2), 69–87.

Gros, H., Thibaut, J. P., & Sander, E. (2021). What we count dictates how we count: A tale of two encodings. Cognition, 212 , 104665.

Gvozdic, K., & Sander, E. (2020). Learning to be an opportunistic word problem solver: Going beyond informal solving strategies. ZDM, 52 (1), 111–123.

Hebart, M. N., Zheng, C. Y., Pereira, F., & Baker, C. I. (2020). Revealing the multidimensional mental representations of natural objects underlying human similarity judgements. Nature Human Behaviour, 4 (11), 1173–1185.

Hegarty, M., & Kozhevnikov, M. (1999). Types of visual–spatial representations and mathematical problem solving. Journal of Educational Psychology, 91 (4), 684.

Hobson, S. M., Trundle, K. C., & Saçkes, M. (2010). Using a planetarium software program to promote conceptual change with young children. Journal of Science Education and Technology, 19 , 165–176.

Hudson, T. (1983). Correspondences and numerical differences between disjoint sets. Child Development, 54 (1), 84–90. https://doi.org/10.2307/112986

Hund, A. M., Kannass, K. N., Bove, R., Fairweather, L., Maydew, M., & Monla, A. (2021). Young children’s understanding of ordinal and spatial labels. Cognitive Development, 58 , 101041.

Iacono, E., Gros, H., & Clément, E. (2022). Training flexible categorization to improve arithmetic problem solving: A school-based intervention with 5th graders. In Culbertson, J., Perfors, A., Rabagliati, H. & Ramenzoni, V. (Eds.), Proceedings of the 44th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society . Cognitive Science Society (Vol. 44).

Jitendra, A. K., & Hoff, K. (1996). The effects of schema-based instruction on the mathematical word-problem solving performance of students with learning disabilities. Journal of Learning Disabilities, 29 , 422–432.

Johnson-Laird, P. N. (2010). Mental models and human reasoning. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 107 (43), 18243–18250. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1012933107

Kintsch, W., & Greeno, J. G. (1985). Understanding and solving word arithmetic problems. Psychological Review, 92 (1), 109.

Kosslyn, S. M., Murphy, G. L., Bemesderfer, M. E., & Feinstein, K. J. (1977). Category and continuum in mental comparisons. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 106 (4), 341.

Lakoff, G., & Núñez, R. E. (2000). Where mathematics comes from: How the embodied mind brings mathematics into being. AMC, 10 (12), 720–733.

Landis, J. R., & Koch, G. G. (1977). The measurement of observer agreement for categorical data. Biometrics, 33 (1), 159–174. https://doi.org/10.2307/2529310

Larkin, J. H., & Simon, H. A. (1987). Why a diagram is (sometimes) worth ten thousand words. Cognitive Science, 11 , 65–99.

Le Corre, M., & Carey, S. (2007). One, two, three, four, nothing more: An investigation of the conceptual sources of the verbal counting principles. Cognition, 105 (2), 395–438.

Lenth, R. V., Buerkner, P., Herve, M., Love, J., Riebl, H., & Singmann, H. (2023). Emmeans: Estimated Marginal Means, Aka Least-Squares Means ; R Package Version 1.8.9; 2023.

Lewis-Peacock, J. A., Drysdale, A. T., & Postle, B. R. (2015). Neural evidence for the flexible control of mental representations. Cerebral Cortex, 25 (10), 3303–3313.

Long, B., Fan, J. E., & Frank, M. C. (2018). Drawings as a window into developmental changes in object representations. In Kalish, C., Rau, M., Zhu, J., & Rogers, T. T. (Eds.), Proceedings of the 40th Annual Conference of Cognitive Science Society (pp. 708–713). Madison, WI: Cognitive Science Society.

Makuuchi, M., Kaminaga, T., & Sugishita, M. (2003). Both parietal lobes are involved in drawing: a functional MRI study and implications for constructional apraxia. Cognitive Brain Research, 16 (3), 338–347.

Martin, S. A., & Bassok, M. (2005). Effects of semantic cues on mathematical modeling: Evidence from word-problem solving and equation construction tasks. Memory & Cognition, 33 , 471–478.

Meade, M. E., Wammes, J. D., & Fernandes, M. A. (2018). Drawing as an encoding tool: Memorial benefits in younger and older adults. Experimental Aging Research, 44 (5), 369–396.

Meyer, C., Barbiers, S., & Weerman, F. (2016). Order and Ordinality: The Acquisition of Cardinals and Ordinals in Dutch. Boston University Conference on Language Development (BUCLD) (40th ed.). Cascadilla.

Mikkilä-Erdmann, M., Södervik, I., Vilppu, H., Kääpä, P., & Olkinuora, E. (2012). First-year medical students’ conceptual understanding of and resistance to conceptual change concerning the central cardiovascular system. Instructional Science, 40 , 745–754.

Miller, S. E., Marcovitch, S., Boseovski, J. J., & Lewkowicz, D. J. (2015). Young children’s ability to use ordinal labels in a spatial search task. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly, 61 (3), 345–361.

Miller, K., Major, S. M., Shu, H., & Zhang, H. (2000). Ordinal knowledge: Number names and number concepts in Chinese and English. Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology/Revue canadienne de psychologie expérimentale, 54 (2), 129.

Ng, S.-F., & Lee, K. (2005). How primary five pupils use the model method to solve word problems. The Mathematics Educator, 9 (1), 60–83.

Orrantia, J., & Múñez, D. (2013). Arithmetic word problem solving: evidence for a magnitude-based mental representation. Memory & Cognition, 41 , 98–108.

Pearson, J., & Kosslyn, S. M. (2015). The heterogeneity of mental representation: Ending the imagery debate. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 112 (33), 10089–10092.

Pinnegar, S., Mangelson, J., Reed, M., & Groves, S. (2011). Exploring preservice teachers’ metaphor plotlines. Teaching and Teacher Education, 27 (3), 639–647.

Reeve, R. A. (1996). The Referential Adequacy of Students’ Visual Analogies of Fractions. Mathematical Cognition, 2 (2), 137–169. https://doi.org/10.1080/135467996387507

Rellensmann, J., Schukajlow, S., & Leopold, C. (2017). Make a drawing. Effects of strategic knowledge, drawing accuracy, and type of drawing on students’ mathematical modelling performance. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 95 , 53–78.

Reusser, K. (1990). From text to situation to equation: Cognitive simulation of understanding and solving mathematical word problems. In H. Mandl, E. De Corte, N. Bennet, & H. F. Friedrich (Eds.), Learning and Instruction, European Research in an International Context (II). Pergamon Press.

Riley, M. S., Greeno, J. G., & Heller, J. 1. (1983). Development of children’s problem-solving ability in arithmetic. The Development of Mathematical Thinking (pp. 153–196). New York: Academic Press.

Roberts, B. R., & Wammes, J. D. (2021). Drawing and memory: Using visual production to alleviate concreteness effects. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 28 , 259–267.

Russell, B. (1919). Introduction to mathematical philosophy . Allen & Unwin.

Sarnecka, B. W., & Lee, M. D. (2009). Levels of number knowledge during early childhood. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 103 (3), 325–337.

Scheibling-Sève, C., Pasquinelli, E., & Sander, E. (2020). Assessing conceptual knowledge through solving arithmetic word problems. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 103 (3), 293–311.

Scheibling-Sève, C., Gvozdic, K., Pasquinelli, E., & Sander, E. (2022). Enhancing cognitive flexibility through a training based on multiple categorization: Developing proportional reasoning in primary school. Journal of Numerical Cognition, 8 (3), 443–472.

Schmeck, A., Mayer, R. E., Opfermann, M., Pfeiffer, V., & Leutner, D. (2014). Drawing pictures during learning from scientific text: Testing the generative drawing effect and the prognostic drawing effect. Contemporary Educational Psychology, 39 (4), 275–286.

Sharp, E., & Shih Dennis, M. (2017). Model drawing strategy for fraction word problem solving of fourth-grade students with learning disabilities. Remedial and Special Education, 38 (3), 181–192.

Shepard, R. N., & Metzler, J. (1971). Mental rotation of three-dimensional objects. Science, 171 (3972), 701–703.

Shulman, K. I. (2000). Clock-drawing: is it the ideal cognitive screening test? International Journal of Geriatric Psychiatry, 15 (6), 548–561.

Shusterman, A., Slusser, E., Halberda, J., & Odic, D. (2016) Acquisition of the cardinal principle coincides with improvement in approximate number system acuity in preschoolers. PLOS ONE, 11(4), e0153072. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0153072

Silver, R. (2009). Identifying children and adolescents with depression: Review of the stimulus drawing task and draw a story research. Art Therapy, 26 (4), 174–180.

Suppes, P. (1972). Axiomatic set theory . Dover Publications.

Thevenot, C. (2010). Arithmetic word problem solving: Evidence for the construction of a mental model. Acta Psychologica, 133 (1), 90–95.

Thevenot, C., & Barrouillet, P. (2015). Arithmetic word problem solving and mental representations. In R. C. Kadosh & A. Dowker (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of numerical cognition (pp. 158–179).

Thevenot, C., & Oakhill, J. (2005). The strategic use of alternative representations in arithmetic word problem solving. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology Section A, 58 (7), 1311–1323.

Thevenot, C., & Oakhill, J. (2006). Representations and strategies for solving dynamic and static arithmetic word problems: The role of working memory capacities. European Journal of Cognitive Psychology, 18 (5), 756–775.

Thom, J. S., & McGarvey, L. M. (2015). The act and artifact of drawing (s): observing geometric thinking with, in, and through children’s drawings. ZDM, 47 , 465–481.

Thomas, G. V., & Jolley, R. P. (1998). Drawing conclusions: A re-examination of empirical and conceptual bases for psychological evaluation of children from their drawings. British Journal of Clinical Psychology, 37 (2), 127–139.

Trundle, K., Atwood, R., & Christopher, J. (2007). Fourth-grade elementary students’ conceptions of standards-based lunar concepts. International Journal of Science Education, 29 (5), 595–616.

Tunç-Pekkan, Z. (2015). An analysis of elementary school children’s fractional knowledge depicted with circle, rectangle, and number line representations. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 89 , 419–441.

Ucar, S., Trundle, K. C., & Krissek, L. (2011). Inquiry-based instruction with archived, online data: An intervention study with preservice teachers. Research in Science Education, 41 , 261–282.

Uesaka, Y., Manalo, E., & Ichikawa, S. I. (2010). The effects of perception of efficacy and diagram construction skills on students’ spontaneous use of diagrams when solving math word problems. Diagrams 2010, Portland, OR, USA, August 9-11, 2010 (pp. 197–211). Springer Berlin Heidelberg.

Van Essen, G. V., & Hamaker, C. (1990). Using self-generated drawings to solve arithmetic word problems. The Journal of Educational Research, 83 (6), 301–312.

Van Garderen, D., & Montague, M. (2003). Visual-spatial representation, mathematical problem solving, and students of varying abilities. Learning Disabilities Research & Practice, 18 (4), 246–254.

Van Meter, P., & Garner, J. (2005). The promise and practice of learner-generated drawing: Literature review and synthesis. Educational psychology review, 17 , 285–325.

Verschaffel, L. (2016). Get the picture? On the role of graphical representations in the solution of mathematical word problems. In  Plenary lecture at the Conference of the EARLI SIG 2, Comprehension of Text and Graphics, University of Geneva, Geneva, Switzerland .

Verschaffel, L., De Corte, E., & Vierstraete, H. (1999). Upper elementary school pupils’ difficulties in modeling and solving nonstandard additive word problems involving ordinal numbers. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 30 (3), 265–285.

Verschaffel, L., Schukajlow, S., Star, J., & Van Dooren, W. (2020). Word problems in mathematics education: A survey. ZDM, 52 , 1–16.

Vosniadou, S., & Brewer, W. F. (1992). Mental models of the earth: A study of conceptual change in childhood. Cognitive Psychology, 24 (4), 535–585.

Wammes, J. D., Meade, M. E., & Fernandes, M. A. (2016). The drawing effect: Evidence for reliable and robust memory benefits in free recall. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 69 (9), 1752–1776.

Wammes, J. D., Meade, M. E., & Fernandes, M. A. (2017). Learning terms and definitions: Drawing and the role of elaborative encoding. Acta Psychologica, 179 , 104–113.

Wammes, J. D., Meade, M. E., & Fernandes, M. A. (2018). Creating a recollection-based memory through drawing. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 44 (5), 734.

PubMed   Google Scholar  

Wasner, M., Moeller, K., Fischer, M. H., & Nuerk, H. C. (2015). Related but not the same: Ordinality, cardinality and 1-to-1 correspondence in finger-based numerical representations. Journal of Cognitive Psychology, 27 (4), 426–441.

Wechsler, D. (2009). WMS-IV: Wechsler memory scale (4th ed.). Pearson.

Weinman, J., Petrie, K. J., Moss-Morris, R., & Horne, R. (1996). The illness perception questionnaire: a new method for assessing the cognitive representation of illness. Psychology and Health, 11 (3), 431–445.

Westenskow, A., Moyer-Packenham, P., Anderson-Pence, K., Shumway, J., & Jordan, K. (2014). Cute drawings? The disconnect between students’ pictorial representations and their mathematics responses to fraction questions. Revista Internacional de Pesquisa em Educação Matemática, 4 (1), 81–105.

Wu, S. P., & Rau, M. A. (2019). How students learn content in science, technology, engineering, and mathematics (STEM) through drawing activities. Educational Psychology Review, 31 , 87–120.

Wynn, K. (1992). Addition and subtraction by human infants. Nature, 358 (6389), 749–750.

Yoshida, H., & Shinmachi, Y. (1999). The influence of instructional intervention on children’s understanding of fractions. Japanese Psychological Research, 41 (4), 218–228.

Download references

This research was supported by grants from the Regional Council of Burgundy, Paris Feder Grants (20159201AAO050S02982 & 20169201AAO050S01845), the Experimental Fund for the Youth and French Ministry of Education (HAP10-CRE-EXPE-S1), and from the French Ministry of Education and Future Investment Plan (CS-032-15-836-ARITHM-0).

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

CY Cergy Paris University, Paragraphe Lab, Gennevilliers, France

Hippolyte Gros

Université de Bourgogne, LEAD-CNRS UMR 5022, Dijon, France

Jean-Pierre Thibaut

University of Geneva, IDEA Lab, Geneva, Switzerland

Emmanuel Sander

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hippolyte Gros .

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of interest.

We have no conflicts of interest to disclose.

Ethics approval

This research was approved by the ethics committee of the University of Geneva (decision n° PSE.20181104.18).

Consent to participate

All participants gave informed consent to participate in the study.

Additional information

Publisher's note.

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Open Practices Statement

All data and materials for this study are available online on OSF at https://osf.io/nhp4e/?view_only=6a5e4fd4dedb4811a994030b988033a8 .

Supplementary Information

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

Supplementary file1 (DOCX 2195 KB)

Rights and permissions.

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Gros, H., Thibaut, JP. & Sander, E. Uncovering the interplay between drawings, mental representations, and arithmetic problem-solving strategies in children and adults. Mem Cogn (2024). https://doi.org/10.3758/s13421-024-01523-w

Download citation

Accepted : 14 January 2024

Published : 12 February 2024

DOI : https://doi.org/10.3758/s13421-024-01523-w

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Context effects
  • Mathematical cognition
  • Mental models
  • Problem solving
  • Find a journal
  • Publish with us
  • Track your research

COMMENTS

  1. Mental representation

    A mental representation (or cognitive representation), in philosophy of mind, cognitive psychology, neuroscience, and cognitive science, is a hypothetical internal cognitive symbol that represents external reality or its abstractions.. Mental representation is the mental imagery of things that are not actually present to the senses. In contemporary philosophy, specifically in fields of ...

  2. Mental Representation

    The notion of a "mental representation" is, arguably, in the first instance a theoretical construct of cognitive science. As such, it is a basic concept of the Computational Theory of Mind, according to which cognitive states and processes are constituted by the occurrence, transformation and storage (in the mind/brain) of information-bearing structures (representations) of one kind or ...

  3. Drawing as a versatile cognitive tool

    Drawing is a cognitive tool that makes the invisible contents of mental life visible. Humans use this tool to produce a remarkable variety of pictures, from realistic portraits to schematic diagrams.

  4. Introduction

    This volume collects original writings on the nature and role of mental representations in cognitive science. In this introduction we will first sketch out the contours of the notion of mental representation as used in cognitive science, then briefly present three debates centered around this notion, and finally give an overview of the papers ...

  5. PDF Overview Psychology of knowledge representation

    Every cognitive enterprise involves some form of knowledge representation. Humans represent information about the external world and internal mental states, like beliefs and desires, and use this information to meet goals (e.g., classification or problem solving). Unfortunately, researchers do not have direct access to mental representations.

  6. Insights into embodied cognition and mental imagery from ...

    Mental representations allow humans to think about, remember and communicate about an infinite number of concepts. A key question within cognitive psychology is how the mind stores and accesses ...

  7. The Concept of Representation

    This chapter reviews representational concepts from a psychological perspective. It begins with a discussion of defining characteristics and controversial issues associated with the concept, followed by a summary of the various forms it has taken in the history of psychology. This conceptual analysis provides the background for an evaluation in ...

  8. What Is a Theory of Mental Representation?

    representation as it is used by the best cognitive science we have available. So on this account, a theory of mental representation begins as part of the cognitive psy- chology of cognitive science, though it may end up contributing to the conceptual foundations of the science it sets out to describe.

  9. Mental Representations and Their Analysis: An Epistemological

    Abstract. It is widely accepted that mental representations (e.g., mental models and other internal cognitive structures) play a key role in the development of knowledge and expertise. This is especially true in problem-solving domains that involve many interacting components (e.g., complex dynamic systems). However, mental representations are ...

  10. Representation in Cognitive Science

    The representational theory of mind (RTM) has given us the powerful insight that thinking consists of the processing of mental representations. Behaviour is the result of these cognitive processes and makes sense in the light of their contents. There is no widely accepted account of how representations get their content - of the metaphysics ...

  11. What Are Mental Representations? (Philosophy of Mind)

    The topic of this book is mental representation, a theoretical concept that lies at the core of cognitive science. Together with the idea that thinking is analogous to computational processing, this concept is responsible for the cognitive turn in the sciences of the mind and brain since the 1950s. Conceiving of cognitive processes (such as perception, reasoning, and motor control) as ...

  12. Defining neural 'representation'

    Defining neural 'representation'. Neuroscientists frequently say that neural activity 'represents' certain phenomena. PIK Professor Konrad Kording and postdoc Ben Baker led a study that took a philosophical approach to tease out what the term means. Neuroscientists use the word "represent" to encompass multifaceted relationships ...

  13. A tutorial on capturing mental representations through drawing and

    When we draw, we are depicting a rich mental representation reflecting a memory, percept, schema, imagination, or feeling. In spite of the abundance of data created by drawings, drawings are rarely used as an output measure in the field of psychology, due to concerns about their large variance and their difficulty of quantification. However, recent work leveraging pen-tracking, computer vision ...

  14. Mental Representation Explained with Examples—Viquepedia

    A mental representation is an unobservable internal code for a physical object (usually instantiated in the brain by neural structures) that possesses semantic properties. Being a physical object in the brain allows mental representations to participate in the causal processes underlying cognition. It is helpful to contrast a mental ...

  15. Mental Representation and the Cognitive Architecture of ...

    The aim of this paper is to understand the functional role of mental representations and intentionality in skilled actions from a systems related perspective. Therefore, we will evaluate the function of representation and then discuss the cognitive architecture of skilled actions in more depth. We are going to describe the building blocks and levels of the action system that enable us to ...

  16. Solved Another name for a mental representation is cognitive

    Question: Another name for a mental representation is cognitive sketch. Another name for a mental representation is cognitive sketch. Here's the best way to solve it.

  17. Representation in Cognitive Science

    Drawing on this cutting-edge research, Nicholas Shea uses a series of case studies from the cognitive sciences to develop a naturalistic account of the nature of mental representation. His approach is distinctive in focusing firmly on the 'subpersonal' representations that pervade so much of cognitive science.

  18. Mental Representation

    The notion of a "mental representation" is, arguably, in the first instance a theoretical construct of cognitive science. As such, it is a basic concept of the Computational Theory of Mind, according to which cognitive states and processes are constituted by the occurrence, transformation and storage (in the mind/brain) of information-bearing ...

  19. PDF analog mental representation

    representation R of a number Q is analog if and only if: There is some property P of R (the representational medium) such that the quantity or amount of P determines Q. As Q increases (or decreases) by an amount d, P increases (or decreases) as a linear function of Q + d (or Q d) -. (Maley, 2011, p. 123).

  20. Introduction. Mental Representation in Cognitive Science and ...

    Methodological considerations about empirical, i.e. applied, phenomenology are followed by a presentation of the exploratory study in which I used pictorial displays that have a picture within another picture. Drawing on the theoretical clarifications of the outline of a phenomenology of mental representation in the present study, some findings ...

  21. Analog mental representation

    Abstract. Over the past 50 years, philosophers and psychologists have perennially argued for the existence of analog mental representations of one type or another. This study critically reviews a number of these arguments as they pertain to three different types of mental representation: perceptual representations, imagery representations, and ...

  22. Another word for MENTAL REPRESENTATION > Synonyms & Antonyms

    Similar words for Mental Representation. Definition: noun. ['ˌrɛprəzɛnˈteɪʃən'] a creation that is a visual or tangible rendering of someone or something.

  23. Uncovering the interplay between drawings, mental representations, and

    There is an ongoing debate in the scientific community regarding the nature and role of the mental representations involved in solving arithmetic word problems. In this study, we took a closer look at the interplay between mental representations, drawing production, and strategy choice. We used dual-strategy isomorphic word problems sharing the same mathematical structure, but differing in the ...

  24. Applied Sciences

    Participants were supposed to rely on their mental representation of the environment. ... A further analysis was performed to investigate the effect of map orientation on survey knowledge regarding cognitive style. Another repeated measures ANOVA was conducted on each factor of sketch map data with map orientation (North-Up vs. Forward-Up) as a ...